•  43
    Self-Love or Diffidence? Malebranche and Hume on the Love of Fame
    Journal of Modern Philosophy 4 (1): 2. 2022.
    Hume’s discussion of pride and sympathy in the _Treatise_ shows direct engagement with Malebranche’s discussion of ‘imitation’ in the _Search_. For Malebranche, imitation—both of passions and belief—and our tendency to judge ourselves by comparison, generate the passion of pride or grandeur, which plays a useful social role. However, as both cause and effect of the admiration of others, grandeur is ungrounded and thus imaginary. Hume disagrees. He invokes the principle of sympathy to explain how…Read more
  •  19
    Book 1 of Hume’s A Treatise of Human Nature was reshaped into the first Enquiry, while the second Enquiry further develops some themes from Book 3. What became of Book 2, “Of the Passions”? Did Hume never extend his thinking in that area? Amyas Merivale notes that the standard answer to that question is that Hume did not do much in the way of rethinking T2 beyond selecting a few passages to excerpt, almost verbatim, in his “Dissertation on the Passions.” In this fine, wide-ranging, scrupulously …Read more
  •  58
    Events and Their Names
    Philosophical Review 101 (2): 416. 1992.
  •  19
  •  10
    The Possibility of Weakness of Will, by Robert Dunn (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 51 (2): 451-455. 1991.
  •  445
    What is Wrong with Weakness of Will?
    Journal of Philosophy 103 (6): 284-311. 2006.
    Many would say that unlike other failures of practical rationality, which can be difficult to recognize, weakness of will wears its rational defect on its sleeve. Whenever we judge that it would be best not to do x, while intentionally doing x without relinquishing this judgment, we condemn quite explicitly the intention on which we act. This observation gives rise to the attractive idea that weak-willed agents indict themselves of irrationality as they fail to comply with their own practical …Read more
  •  13
    Colloquium 6
    Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 6 (1): 228-239. 1990.
  •  4
    Omissions and Other Acts
    Dissertation, Princeton University. 1985.
    Philosophical discussion of the topic of intentional agency has often focused on questions about the nature of the events which are intentional actions. This event-oriented approach cannot yield an adequate account of human agency because it cannot accommodate negative acts, or acts of omission. Agents may act intentionally by omitting to act, but many such acts of omission cannot be identified with any event consisting of a bodily movement. This dissertation is an attempt to develop an account …Read more
  •  44
    Fruitless Remorses
    Hume Studies 40 (2): 143-167. 2014.
    Familiarity with the doctrines presented in Richard Allestree’s devotional work The Whole Duty of Man (1658), which Hume reported having read as a boy, can illuminate the strategy of argument Hume employs in Treatise 2.1.6–2.1.8 to undermine views he attributes to “the vulgar systems of ethicks.” Hume’s explicit critique of the view that pride is a sin and humility a virtue in Treatise 2.1.7 relies on assumptions that are already present in Allestree’s account of pride and humility and are descr…Read more
  •  23
    Commentary on Heinaman
    Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 12 (1): 112-123. 1996.
  •  107
    Responsibility and control: A theory of moral responsibility
    Philosophical Review 109 (2): 267-270. 2000.
    John Fischer and Mark Ravizza defend in this book a painstakingly constructed analysis of what they take to be a core condition of moral responsibility: the notion of guidance control. The volume usefully collects in one place ideas and arguments the authors have previously published in singly or jointly authored works on this and related topics, as well as various refinements to those views and some suggestive discussions that aim to show how their account of guidance control might fit into a m…Read more
  •  269
    Doing away with double effect
    Ethics 111 (2): 219-255. 2001.
    I will introduce six constraints that should guide the formulation and use of DE. One goal in listing them is to engage in dialectical fair play by ruling out criticisms of the doctrine that are directed at misformulations of DE or that result from misapplications of it. Each of these constraints should be acceptable to any proponent of DE. Yet when these constraints on the application of DE are respected, it becomes clear that many of the examples provided as illustrations of DE actually illust…Read more
  •  357
    Doctrine of double effect
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2008.
    The doctrine (or principle) of double effect is often invoked to explain the permissibility of an action that causes a serious harm, such as the death of a human being, as a side effect of promoting some good end. According to the principle of double effect, sometimes it is permissible to cause a harm as a side effect (or “double effect”) of bringing about a good result even though it would not be permissible to cause such a harm as a means to bringing about the same good end. Does the principl…Read more
  •  36
    The Possibility of Weakness of Will, by Robert Dunn (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 51 (2): 451-455. 1991.
  •  12
    Commentary on Robert Heinaman’s “Aristotle on Praxis and Activity”
    Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 6 (1): 228-239. 1990.