•  992
    Art, Beauty and Morality
    In Silvia Caprioglio Panizza & Mark Hopwood (eds.), Murdochian Mind, Routledge. 2022.
    In this chapter, we examine Iris Murdoch’s views about art. We highlight continuities and differences between her views on art and aesthetics, and those of Plato, Kant, and Freud. We argue that Murdoch’s views about art, though traditionally linked to Plato, are more compatible with Kant’s thought than has been acknowledged—though with his ethics rather than his aesthetics. Murdoch shows Plato’s influence in her idea that beauty is the good in a different guise. However, Murdoch shows a more Kan…Read more
  •  212
    The art of improvisation and the aesthetics of imperfection
    British Journal of Aesthetics 40 (1): 168-185. 2000.
  •  168
    In The Blue Book, Wittgenstein defined a category of uses of “I” which he termed “I”-as-subject, contrasting them with “I”-as-object uses. The hallmark of this category is immunity to error through misidentification (IEM). This article extends Wittgenstein’s characterisation to the case of memory-judgments, discusses the significance of IEM for self-consciousness—developing the idea that having a first-person thought involves thinking about oneself in a distinctive way in which one cannot think …Read more
  •  146
    Music and the aural arts
    British Journal of Aesthetics 47 (1): 46-63. 2007.
    The visual arts include painting, sculpture, photography, video, and film. But many people would argue that music is the universal or only art of sound. In the modernist era, Western art music has incorporated unpitched sounds or ‘noise’, and I pursue the question of whether this process allows space for a non-musical soundart. Are there non-musical arts of sound—is there an art phonography, for instance, to parallel art photography? At the same time, I attempt a characterization of music, contr…Read more
  •  92
    'Scottish commonsense' about memory: A defence of Thomas Reid's direct knowledge account
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 81 (2): 229-245. 2003.
    Reid rejects the image theory --the representative or indirect realist position--that memory-judgements are inferred from or otherwise justified by a present image or introspectible state. He also rejects the trace theory , which regards memories as essentially traces in the brain. In contrast he argues for a direct knowledge account in which personal memory yields unmediated knowledge of the past. He asserts the reliability of memory, not in currently fashionable terms as a reliable belief-form…Read more
  •  90
  •  77
    The authority of avowals and the concept of belief
    European Journal of Philosophy 8 (1): 20-39. 2000.
    The pervasive dispositional model of belief is misguided. It fails to acknowledge the authority of first‐person ascriptions or avowals of belief, and the “decision principle”– that having decided the question whether p, there is, for me, no further question whether I believe that p. The dilemma is how one can have immediate knowledge of a state extended in time; its resolution lies in the expressive character of avowals – which does not imply a non‐assertoric thesis – and their non‐cognitive sta…Read more
  •  69
    Intention and the authority of avowals
    Philosophical Explorations 11 (1). 2008.
    There is a common assumption that intention is a complex behavioural disposition, or a motivational state underlying such a disposition. Associated with this position is the apparently commonsense view that an avowal of intention is a direct report of an inner motivational state, and indirectly an expression of a belief that it is likely that one will A. A central claim of this article is that the dispositional or motivational model is mistaken since it cannot acknowledge either the future-direc…Read more
  •  68
    The art of recording and the aesthetics of perfection
    British Journal of Aesthetics 43 (4): 345-362. 2003.
    Recording has transformed the nature of music as an art by reconfiguring the opposition between the aesthetics of perfection and imperfection. A precursor article, ‘The Art of Improvisation and the Aesthetics of Imperfection’, contrasted the perfectionist aesthetic of the ‘work-concept’ with the imperfectionist aesthetic of improvisation. Imperfectionist approaches to recording are purist in wanting to maintain the diachronic and synchronic integrity of the performance, which perfectionist recor…Read more
  •  67
    The Aesthetics of Western Art Music
    Philosophical Books 40 (3): 145-159. 1999.
    Book reviewed in this article: Roger Scruton, The Aesthetics of Music.
  •  62
    Scruton's philosophy of culture: Elitism, populism, and classic art
    British Journal of Aesthetics 49 (4): 389-404. 2009.
    Scruton is a self-confessed elitist for whom culture is ‘the creation and creator of elites’, though its meaning ‘lies in emotions and aspirations that are common to all’. This article argues that one can uphold his humane conception of the value of high culture without endorsing elitism. It develops a surprisingly unelitist strand in Scruton's thinking into a meritocratic middle way between elitism and populism, in order to explain why art is in some sense an elite product, but with communal re…Read more
  •  51
    II—Rhythm and Stasis: A Major and Almost Entirely Neglected Philosophical Problem
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 111 (1pt1): 25-42. 2011.
    This article develops a dynamic account of rhythm as ‘order‐in‐movement’ that opposes static accounts of rhythm as abstract time, as essentially a pattern of possibly unstressed sounds and silences. This dynamic account is humanistic: it focuses on music as a humanly‐produced, sonorous phenomenon, privileging the human as opposed to the abstract, or the organic or mechanical. It defends the claim that movement is the most fundamental conceptualization of music—the basic category in terms of whic…Read more
  •  44
    Review: John Stuart Mill (review)
    Mind 114 (454): 400-402. 2005.
  •  43
    © The Author 2017. Published by Oxford University Press on behalf of The Analysis Trust. All rights reserved. For Permissions, please email: [email protected] this very wide-ranging and absorbing monograph, Nicholas Wolterstorff argues that modern aestheticians ignore the varieties of engagement with art, in an exclusive focus on disinterested attention. This, he argues, is because they assume the ‘grand narrative concerning art in the modern world’. According to Wolterstorff, this …Read more
  •  41
    Artistic Truth
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 71 229-261. 2012.
    According to Wittgenstein, in the remarks collected as Culture and Value , ‘People nowadays think, scientists are there to instruct them, poets, musicians etc. to entertain them. That the latter have something to teach them; that never occurs to them.’ 18th and early 19th century art-lovers would have taken a very different view. Dr. Johnson assumed that the poets had truths to impart, while Hegel insisted that ‘In art we have to do not with any agreeable or useful child's play, but with an unfo…Read more
  •  35
    The Aesthetics of Imperfection Reconceived: Improvisations, Compositions, and Mistakes
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 78 (3): 289-302. 2020.
    ABSTRACT Ted Gioia associated the “aesthetics of imperfection” with improvised music. In an earlier article, I extended it to all musical performance. This article reconceives my discussion, offering more precise analyses: The aesthetics of imperfection is now argued to involve open, spontaneous response to contingencies of performance or production, reacting positively to idiosyncratic instruments; apparent failings in performance, and so on. Perfectionists, in contrast, prefer a planning model…Read more
  •  34
    This article develops a Wittgensteinian treatment of the relationship between art and entertainment, combining universal and historically conditioned features.
  •  32
    Scruton's Aesthetics (edited book)
    with Nick Zangwill
    Palgrave-Macmillan. 2012.
    Scruton's Aesthetics is a comprehensive critical evaluation of one of the major aestheticians of our age. The lead essay by Scruton is followed by fourteen essays by international commentators plus Scruton's reply. All discuss matters of enduring importance.
  •  30
    Aesthetics and music * by Andy Hamilton (review)
    Analysis 69 (2): 397-398. 2007.
    Aesthetics and Music is a rich and interesting study. Hamilton's approach is innovative. He interleaves chapters on the history of philosophical thought about music with more theoretical discussions of music, sound, rhythm and improvisation, but does not cover the work–performance relation, depiction or expression. He draws on an atypically broad range of examples, including avant-garde, medieval, non-Western and jazz. The assumptions are humanist: ‘I wish to argue for an aesthetic conception of…Read more
  •  23
    Rhythm and Movement: The Conceptual Interdependence of Music, Dance, and Poetry
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 44 (1): 161-182. 2019.
    Midwest Studies In Philosophy, EarlyView.
  •  20
    Wittgenstein had little to say directly on philosophy of history. But some pertinent remarks in _On Certainty_ have received little attention, apart from in Elizabeth Anscombe's short article on Hume and Julius Caesar. That article acknowledges its debt to _On Certainty,_ which responses to Anscombe have failed to recognise. Wittgenstein focuses in _On Certainty_ on apparently empirical propositions that seem to be certainties, but in fact form a rule-like framework for judging. I have called th…Read more