•  21
    7. Being Properly Affected: Virtues and Feelings in Aristotle's Ethics
    In Amélie Rorty (ed.), Essays on Aristotle’s Ethics, University of California Press. pp. 103-116. 1980.
  •  25
    Colloquium 3 Why the Gods Love what is Holy: Euthyphro 10–11
    Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 31 (1): 95-112. 2016.
    In Plato’s Euthyphro, an early response to Socrates’ question, What is holiness? defines holiness as what is loved by all the gods. Socrates responds to this proposed definition with an argument that is often misunderstood. English translations, in particular, finding it difficult to represent the argument’s distinction between finite passive constructions—‘x is loved’—and passive participial constructions—‘x is beloved’—represent the argument instead as concerned with a distinction between acti…Read more
  •  1
    The Activity of Being in Aristotle's Metaphysics
    In M. L. Eds and Gill D. Charles T. Scaltsas (ed.), Unity, Identity, and Explanation in Aristotle's Metaphysics, Oxford University Press. pp. 195-213. 1994.
  •  216
    Aristotle's definition of motion
    Phronesis 14 (1): 40-62. 1969.
  •  179
    Perceiving that we perceive: On the soul III,
    Philosophical Review 84 (4): 499-519. 1975.
  •  10
    Mechanisms in ancient philosophy of science
    Perspectives on Science 12 (3): 244-261. 2004.
    . This essay considers the place of mechanisms in ancient theories of science. It might seem therefore to promise a meager discussion, since the importance of mechanisms in contemporary scientific explanation is the product of a revolution in scientific thinking connected with the late Renaissance and its mechanization of nature. Indeed the conception of astronomy as devoted merely to “saving the appearances” without reference to the physics of planetary motion might seem an instance of ancient …Read more
  •  35
    Chapter 7. Aristotle’s Prime Mover
    In Mary Louise Gill & James G. Lennox (eds.), Self-Motion: From Aristotle to Newton, Princeton University Press. pp. 135-154. 2017.
  •  51
    Understanding “what something is” has long occupied philosophers, and no Western thinker has had more influence on the nature of being than Aristotle. Focusing on a reinterpretation of the concept of energeia as “activity,” Aryeh Kosman reexamines Aristotle’s ontology and some of our most basic assumptions about the great philosopher’s thought.
  •  1
    Commentary on Johansen
    Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 21. 2005.
  •  39
    Colloquium 3: The Faces of Justice. Difference, Equality, and Integrity in Plato’s Republic
    Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 20 (1): 153-175. 2005.
  •  1
    What Does the Maker Mind Make?
    In Martha Craven Nussbaum & Amélie Rorty (eds.), Essays on Aristotle's De anima, Oxford University Press. pp. 343-358. 1995 [1992].
  •  16
    Commentary on Teloh
    Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 2 (1): 39-43. 1986.
  •  171
    Ontological Differences
    Epoché: A Journal for the History of Philosophy 11 (2): 421-434. 2007.
    Aristotle’s discussions, in Metaphysics Delta 7 and 8, of things designated by the terms we translate ‘being’ and ‘substance’ are revealing in several respects. The discussion in chapter 7 reveals the centrality in his thinking of the distinction between in itself and accidental being, a distinction different from that between substance and the other categories. The discussion in chapter 8 in turn reveals not only two related criteria for calling things substance, but a distinction as well betwe…Read more
  •  22
    Virtues of Thought
    Harvard. 2013.
    Exploring what two foundational figures, Plato and Aristotle, have to say about the nature of human awareness and understanding, Aryeh Kosman concludes that ultimately the virtues of thought are to be found in the joys and satisfactions that come from thinking philosophically, whether we engage in it ourselves or witness others' participation.
  •  32
    Chapter Five
    Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 3 (1): 165-188. 1987.
  •  2
    The Divine in Aristotle's Ethics
    Animus 13 101-107. 2009.
    God plays several roles in Aristotle’s account of a good life, none explicitly. A principle of good in general and of human good in particular, God is specifically a principle of intelligent agency, of our ability to choose and thus shape and act in accordance with virtue. God explains well-being not obviously a result of virtuous action: the divine can be seen as the source of blessed lives. Similarly, the divine can figure moral luck, the way lives turn out despite our choices. Finally, God is…Read more
  •  159
    Aristotle on the Desirability of Friends
    Ancient Philosophy 24 (1): 135-154. 2004.
  •  37
    Aristotle's First Predicament
    Review of Metaphysics 20 (3). 1967.
    Alternatively, we might attend not to the different answers appropriate to different questions asked about the same entity, but to the different answers which result when, about different entities, the same question is asked repeatedly, the question "What is it?" What is Socrates? a man; what is a man? an animal; and so on, branch by branch up the Porphyrian tree, until we reach "substance." Each ultimate answer will signify a supreme and irreducible genus of entity, not a type of predicate, but…Read more
  •  74
    Aristotelian metaphysics and biology: Furth's substance, form and psyche (review)
    Philosophical Studies 94 (1-2): 57-68. 1999.