•  2008
    Education for Moral Integrity
    Journal of Philosophy of Education 35 (2): 219-235. 2001.
    This paper focuses on coherence and consistency as elements of moral integrity, arguing that several kinds of—mostly second-order—virtues contribute to establishing coherence and consistency in a person's judgements and behaviour. The virtues relevant for integrity always accompany other, substantive virtues, and their associated values, principles and rules. In moral education we teach children all kinds of substantive virtues with integrity as our goal. Nevertheless, many adults do not attain …Read more
  •  1709
    De dubbele subjectiviteit van het geweten en noodzaak van toetsing van gewetensbezwaren
    Algemeen Nederlands Tijdschrift voor Wijsbegeerte 109 (3): 329-345. 2017.
    The double subjectivity of conscience and the need to test conscientious objections Abstract In spite of the collapse of the traditional objective concept of conscience and the subsequent subjectivation of conscience, conscientious objections are still often considered as a valid ground for exemption from legal and professional obligations. Conscientious objections are seen as more serious than ordinary moral objections. It is not evident why this is so. I argue, with Niklas Luhmann, that the fu…Read more
  •  1600
    Moral intuitions, moral expertise and moral reasoning
    Journal of Philosophy of Education 43 (4): 597-613. 2009.
    In this article I examine the consequences of the dominance of intuitive thinking in moral judging and deciding for the role of moral reasoning in moral education. I argue that evidence for the reliability of moral intuitions is lacking. We cannot determine when we can trust our intuitive moral judgements. Deliberate and critical reasoning is needed, but it cannot replace intuitive thinking. Following Robin Hogarth, I argue that intuitive judgements can be improved. The expertise model for moral…Read more
  •  415
    What is empirical ethics?
    Ethik in der Medizin 21 (3): 187-199. 2009.
    Empirische Ethik ist ein relativ neues Vorgehen in der Ethikforschung, das vor allem in der Medizinethik angewandt wird. Dieser Beitrag bespricht die kennzeichnenden Charakteristika der empirischen Ethik und unterscheidet zwischen generalistischer und kontextualistischer empirischer Ethik. Zuerst werden verschiedene Beispiele beider Arten von empirischer Ethik vorgestellt, danach werden für beide Ansätze mögliche Schwachpunkte diskutiert. Die Schlussfolgerung des Beitrages besteht darin, dass da…Read more
  •  335
    Empirical Ethics and the Special Status of Practitioners' Judgements
    Ethical Perspectives 17 (2): 203-230. 2010.
    According to some proponents of an empirical medical ethics, medical ethics should take the experience, insights, and arguments of doctors and other medical practitioners as their point of departure. Medical practitioners are supposed to have ‘moral wisdom.’ In this view, the moral beliefs of medical practitioners have a special status. In sections I-IV, I discuss two possible defences of such a status. The first defence is based on the special status of the moral beliefs of the health professio…Read more
  •  330
    Naturalness: Beyond animal welfare
    Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 15 (2): 171-186. 2002.
    There is an ongoing debate in animalethics on the meaning and scope of animalwelfare. In certain broader views, leading anatural life through the development of naturalcapabilities is also headed under the conceptof animal welfare. I argue that a concern forthe development of natural capabilities of ananimal such as expressed when living freelyshould be distinguished from the preservationof the naturalness of its behavior andappearance. However, it is not always clearwhere a plea for natural liv…Read more
  •  325
    Moral Animals and Moral Responsibility
    Les ateliers de l'éthique/The Ethics Forum 10 (2): 38-59. 2015.
    Albert Musschenga | : The central question of this article is, Are animals morally responsible for what they do? Answering this question requires a careful, step-by-step argument. In sections 1 and 2, I explain what morality is, and that having a morality means following moral rules or norms. In sections 3 and 4, I argue that some animals show not just regularities in their social behaviour, but can be rightly said to follow social norms. But are the norms they follow also moral norms? In sectio…Read more
  •  304
    Intrinsic value as a reason for the preservation of minority cultures
    Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 1 (2): 201-225. 1998.
    In the Netherlands, the policy of supporting the efforts of ethnic-cultural minorities to express and preserve their cultural distinctiveness, is nowadays considered as problematic because it might interfere with their integration into the wider society. The primary aim is now to reduce these groups' unemployment rate and to stimulate their participation in the wider society. In this article I consider how the notion of the intrinsic value of cultures, if sensible, might affect the policy regard…Read more
  •  274
    The epistemic value of intuitive moral judgements
    Philosophical Explorations 13 (2): 113-128. 2010.
    In this article, I discuss whether intuitive moral judgements have epistemic value. Are they mere expressions of irrational feelings that should be disregarded or should they be taken seriously? In section 2, I discuss the view of some social psychologists that moral intuitions are, like other social intuitions, under certain conditions more reliable than conscious deliberative judgements. In sections 3 and 4, I examine whether intuitive moral judgements can be said not to need inferential justi…Read more
  •  210
    The issue of generality in ethics
    with Wim J. Van der Steen
    Journal of Value Inquiry 26 (4): 511-524. 1992.
    Does ethics have adequate general theories? Our analysis shows that this question does not have a straightforward answer since the key terms are ambiguous. So we should not concentrate on the answer but on the question itself. “Ethics” stands for many things, but we let that pass. “Adequate” may refer to varied arrays of methodological principles which are seldom fully articulated in ethics. “General” is a notion with at least three meanings. Different kinds of generality may be at cross-purpose…Read more
  •  116
    The epistemic value of intuitive moral judgements
    Philosophical Explorations 13 (2): 113-128. 2010.
    In this article, I discuss whether intuitive moral judgements have epistemic value. Are they mere expressions of irrational feelings that should be disregarded or should they be taken seriously? In section 2, I discuss the view of some social psychologists that moral intuitions are, like other social intuitions, under certain conditions more reliable than conscious deliberative judgements. In sections 3 and 4, I examine whether intuitive moral judgements can be said not to need inferential justi…Read more
  •  68
    Moral Progress: an Introduction
    Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 20 (1): 3-15. 2017.
  •  62
    The Debate on Impartiality: An Introduction
    Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 8 (1-2): 1-10. 2005.
  •  49
    From the editors
    with Robert Heeger
    Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 11 (1): 337-337. 2008.
  •  48
    From the editors
    with Robert Heeger
    Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 10 (5): 337-337. 2007.
  •  46
    The promises of moral foundations theory
    Journal of Moral Education 42 (3): 330-345. 2013.
    In this article I examine whether Moral Foundations Theory can fulfil the promises that Haidt claims for the theory: that it will help in developing new approaches to moral education and to the moral conflicts that divide our diverse society. I argue that, first, the model that Haidt suggests for understanding the plurality of moralities—a shared foundation underlying diverse moralities—does not help to overcome conflicts. A better understanding of the nature and background of moral conflicts ca…Read more
  •  42
    Editorial note
    with Robert Heeger
    Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 11 (5): 1-4. 2008.
  •  39
    From the editors
    with Robert Heeger
    Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 9 (3): 337-337. 2006.
  •  39
    From the editors
    with Robert Heeger
    Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 1 (4): 337-337. 1998.
  •  36
    Is There a Problem With False Hope?
    Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 44 (4): 423-441. 2019.
    This article offers a general discussion of the concept of false hope. Its ultimate aim is to clarify the meaning and the relevance of that concept for medicine and medical research. In the first part, the concept of hope is discussed. I argue that hope is more than a combination of a desire and a belief about the probability that the desire will be fulfilled. Imagination and anticipation are as well components of hope. I also discuss if hope implies orientation to action. In the second part, I …Read more
  •  34
    From the editors
    with Robert Heeger
    Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 9 (2): 337-337. 2006.
  •  33
    From the editors
    with Robert Heeger
    Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 8 (3): 337-337. 2005.
  •  31
    From the editors
    with Robert Heeger
    Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 7 (2): 337-337. 2004.
  •  30
    Education for moral integrity
    Journal of Philosophy of Education 35 (2). 2001.
    This paper focuses on coherence and consistency as elements of moral integrity, arguing that several kinds of—mostly second-order—virtues contribute to establishing coherence and consistency in a person's judgements and behaviour. The virtues relevant for integrity always accompany other, substantive virtues, and their associated values, principles and rules. In moral education we teach children all kinds of substantive virtues with integrity as our goal. Nevertheless, many adults do not attain …Read more
  •  25
    From the editors
    with Robert Heeger
    Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 3 (2): 337-337. 2000.
  •  20
    Editorial
    with Robert Heeger
    Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 11 (2): 121-122. 2008.
  •  15
    Identity-neutral and identity-constitutive reasons for preserving nature
    Journal of Applied Philosophy 21 (1). 2004.
    Environmental ethicists will often say that in dealing with natural entities we need the guidance of an ethic rooted in 'the intrinsic value of nature'. They will add that subjectivist value theories are unable to account for the normativity of intrinsic value discourse. This preoccupation with normativity explains why many environmental ethicists favour value objectivism. As I see it, value theories must address not only the problem of normativity but also the problem of motivation. In fact, my…Read more