•  769
    Causal Decision Theory and Decision Instability
    Journal of Philosophy 116 (5): 263-277. 2019.
    The problem of the man who met death in Damascus appeared in the infancy of the theory of rational choice known as causal decision theory. A straightforward, unadorned version of causal decision theory is presented here and applied, along with Brian Skyrms’ deliberation dynamics, to Death in Damascus and similar problems. Decision instability is a fascinating topic, but not a source of difficulty for causal decision theory. Andy Egan’s purported counterexample to causal decision theory, Murde…Read more
  •  726
    A foundation for causal decision theory
    Topoi 5 (1): 3-19. 1986.
    The primary aim of this paper is the presentation of a foundation for causal decision theory. This is worth doing because causal decision theory (CDT) is philosophically the most adequate rational decision theory now available. I will not defend that claim here by elaborate comparison of the theory with all its competitors, but by providing the foundation. This puts the theory on an equal footing with competitors for which foundations have already been given. It turns out that it will also produ…Read more
  •  628
    Dutch Books, Additivity, and Utility Theory
    Philosophical Topics 21 (1): 1-20. 1993.
    One guide to an argument's significance is the number and variety of refutations it attracts. By this measure, the Dutch book argument has considerable importance.2 Of course this measure alone is not a sure guide to locating arguments deserving of our attention—if a decisive refutation has really been given, we are better off pursuing other topics. But the presence of many and varied counterarguments at least suggests that either the refutations are controversial, or that their target admits of…Read more
  •  502
    Deliberation and pragmatic belief
    In Brian Kim & Matthew McGrath (eds.), Pragmatic Encroachment in Epistemology, Routledge. 2019.
    To what extent do our beliefs, and how strongly we hold them, depend upon how they matter to us, on what we take to be at stake on them? The idea that beliefs are sometimes stake-sensitive (Armendt 2008, 2013) is further explored here, with a focus on whether beliefs may be stake-sensitive and rational. In contexts of extended deliberation about what to do, beliefs and assessments of options interact. In some deliberations, a belief about what you will do may rationally influence your estimat…Read more
  •  500
    Pragmatic Interests and Imprecise Belief
    Philosophy of Science 80 (5): 758-768. 2013.
    Does the strength of a particular belief depend upon the significance we attach to it? Do we move from one context to another, remaining in the same doxastic state concerning p yet holding a stronger belief that p in one context than in the other? For that to be so, a doxastic state must have a certain sort of context-sensitive complexity. So the question is about the nature of belief states, as we understand them, or as we think a theory should model them. I explore the idea and how it relates …Read more
  •  468
    Is there a dutch book argument for probability kinematics?
    Philosophy of Science 47 (4): 583-588. 1980.
    Dutch Book arguments have been presented for static belief systems and for belief change by conditionalization. An argument is given here that a rule for belief change which under certain conditions violates probability kinematics will leave the agent open to a Dutch Book.
  •  466
    Stakes and beliefs
    Philosophical Studies 147 (1). 2010.
    The idea that beliefs may be stake-sensitive is explored. This is the idea that the strength with which a single, persistent belief is held may vary and depend upon what the believer takes to be at stake. The stakes in question are tied to the truth of the belief—not, as in Pascal’s wager and other cases, to the belief’s presence. Categorical beliefs and degrees of belief are considered; both kinds of account typically exclude the idea and treat belief as stake-invariant , though an exception is…Read more
  •  413
    Stake-invariant belief
    Acta Analytica 23 (1): 29-43. 2008.
    What can rational deliberation indicate about belief? Belief clearly influences deliberation. The principle that rational belief is stake-invariant rules out at least one way that deliberation might influence belief. The principle is widely, if implicitly, held in work on the epistemology of categorical belief, and it is built into the model of choice-guiding degrees of belief that comes to us from Ramsey and de Finetti. Criticisms of subjective probabilism include challenges to the assumption o…Read more
  •  377
    On Risk and Rationality
    Erkenntnis 79 (S6): 1-9. 2014.
    It is widely held that the influence of risk on rational decisions is not entirely explained by the shape of an agent’s utility curve. Buchak (Erkenntnis, 2013, Risk and rationality, Oxford University Press, Oxford, in press) presents an axiomatic decision theory, risk-weighted expected utility theory (REU), in which decision weights are the agent’s subjective probabilities modified by his risk-function r. REU is briefly described, and the global applicability of r is discussed. Rabin’s (Econome…Read more
  •  221
    Introduction
    Philosophical Studies 147 (1): 1-5. 2010.
    Introduction to 'Skyrmsfest: Papers in Honor of Brian Skyrms' issue of Philosophical Studies, January 2010. Remarks about Brian Skyrms and about the 10 papers in the issue.
  •  80
    Marinoff on evolutionarily stable strategies
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 44 (4): 789-793. 1993.
    Louis Marinoff [1990] criticizes Axelrod and Hamilton's [1981] use of the concept of an evolutionarily stable strategy, and claims to find an inconsistency between their theory for repeated Prisoner's Dilemma games and empirical results. Marinoff seeks to resolve the inconsistency by arguing that Axelrod and Hamilton's model is ill conceived: he purports to prove, contra Axelrod and Hamilton, that no evolutionarily stable strategy exists in the repeated Prisoner's Dilemma. But his argument is fl…Read more
  •  58
    Introduction
    Philosophical Studies 77 (1): 1-6. 1995.
    Introduction to 'Belief and Probability,' issue of Philosophical Studies, January 1995. Remarks on contents, including van Fraassen, 'Belief and the Problem of Ulysses and the Sirens,' Skyrms, 'Strict Coherence, Sigma Coherence and the Metaphysics of Quantity,' Jeffrey, 'Probability Reparation,' de Finetti, 'The Logic of Probability,' Kolmogorov, 'Complete Metric Boolean Algebras,' 4 more.
  •  50
    Impartiality and Causal Decision Theory
    PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1988. 1988.
    Defenders of sophisticated evidential decision theory (EDT) have argued (1) that its failure to provide correct recommendations in problems where the agent believes himself asymmetrically fallible in executing his choices is no flaw of the theory, and (2) that causal decision theory gives incorrect recommendations in certain examples unless it is supplemented with an additional metatickle or ratifiability deliberation mechanism. In the first part of this paper, I argue that both positions are in…Read more
  •  47
    Conditional Preference and Causal Expected Utility
    In W. L. Harper & B. Skyrms (eds.), Causation in Decision, Belief Change, and Statistics, vol. II, Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 3-24. 1988.
    Sequel to Armendt 1986, ‘A Foundation for Causal Decision Theory.’ The representation theorem for causal decision theory is slightly revised, with the addition of a new restriction on lotteries and a new axiom (A7). The discussion gives some emphasis to the way in which appropriate K-partitions are characterized by relations found among the agent’s conditional preferences. The intended interpretation of conditional preference is one that embodies a sensitivity to the agent’s causal beliefs.
  •  43
    Dutch Strategies for Diachronic Rules: When Believers See the Sure Loss Coming
    PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1992. 1992.
    Two criticisms of Dutch strategy arguments are discussed: One says that the arguments fail because agents who know the arguments can use that knowledge to avoid Dutch strategy vulnerability, even though they violate the norm in question. The second consists of cases alleged to be counterexamples to the norms that Dutch strategy arguments defend. The principle of Reflection and its Dutch strategy argument are discussed, but most attention is given to the rule of Conditionalization and to Jeffrey'…Read more
  •  30
    Notes on Philosophy, Probability and Mathematics (review)
    Philosophical Review 103 (4): 713-715. 1994.
    Review of Maria Carla Galavotti (ed), Notes on Philosophy, Probability and Mathematics, 1991, Bibliopolis. Notes are selected from manuscripts by Frank Plumpton Ramsey at the University of Pittsburgh's Hillman Library.
  •  6
    Impartiality and Causal Decision Theory
    PSA Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1988 (1): 326-336. 1988.
    Causal decision theory (CDT) is the best theory of rational choice now available.2 I intend to provide some support for that claim in part I of this paper by responding to two criticisms of CDT. The first criticism says that CDT is superfluous, since it does no better in the problems that matter than does evidential decision theory (EDT) at recommending correct choices. A second criticism says that CDT by itself is flawed: according to this view, there are problems in which CDT makes bad recomme…Read more
  •  5
    Causal Decision Theory
    In Sven Ove Hansson & Vincent F. Hendricks (eds.), Introduction to Formal Philosophy, Springer. pp. 669-691. 2012.
    Causal decision theory is a general theory of rational decision, appropriate for simple or complex decision problems. It is an expected utility theory distinguished by its explicit attention to causal features of decision problems, and by the significance it attaches to those features. When the causal structure of a decision problem is uncomplicated, the recommendations of CDT and other theories generally agree. In more complex cases, however, CDT identifies rational decisions where other theori…Read more
  •  5
    Frank P. Ramsey (1903–1930)
    In A. P. Martinich & David Sosa (eds.), A Companion to Analytic Philosophy, Blackwell. 2001.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Foundations of mathematics Belief and truth Reasonable belief, probability, and knowledge Laws, causality, and theories Notes Bibliography.
  • Rational Decision Theory: The Foundations of Causal Decision Theory
    Dissertation, University of Illinois at Chicago. 1983.
    In recent years rational decision theories such as Richard Jeffrey's, which recommend that an agent act so as to maximize his conditional expected utility, have come under attack on the grounds that they are unable to adequately handle certain kinds of decision problems. Because of their general structure, these problems are sometimes known as "causal counterexamples" to the theories; well-known examples are Newcomb's problem, the Prisoner's Dilemma, and Fisher's smoking gene problem. Several ve…Read more