Cornell University
Sage School of Philosophy
PhD, 1960
Ithaca, New York, United States of America
Areas of Specialization
Epistemology
Philosophy of Action
  •  423
    Self-Evidence
    Logos and Episteme 1 (2): 325-352. 2010.
    ABSTRACT: This paper develops an account of what it is for a proposition to be self- evident to someone, based on the idea that certain propositions are such that to fully understand them is to believe them. It argues that when a proposition p is self-evident to one, one has non-inferential a priori justification for believing that p and, a welcome feature, a justification that does not involve exercising any special sort of intuitive faculty; if, in addition, it is true that p and there exists …Read more
  •  347
    Freedom, responsibility, and agency
    The Journal of Ethics 1 (1): 85-98. 1997.
    This paper first distinguishes three alternative views that adherents to both incompatibilism and PAP may take as to what constitutes an agent''s determining or controlling her action (if it''s not the action''s being deterministically caused by antecedent events): the indeterministic-causation view, the agent-causation view, and "simple indeterminism." The bulk of the paper focusses on the dispute between simple indeterminism - the view that the occurrence of a simple mental event is determined…Read more
  •  254
    On Action
    Cambridge University Press. 1990.
    This book deals with foundational issues in the theory of the nature of action, the intentionality of action, the compatibility of freedom of action with determinism, and the explantion of action. Ginet's is a volitional view: that every action has as its core a 'simple' mental action. He develops a sophisticated account of the individuation of actions and also propounds a challenging version of the view that freedom of action is incompatible with determinism.
  •  189
    The paper explicates a version of dispositionalism and defends it against Kripke's objections (in his "Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language") that 1) it leaves out the normative aspect of a rule, 2) it cannot account for the directness of the knowledge one has of what one meant, and 3) regarding rules for computable functions of numbers, a) there are numbers beyond one's capacity to consider and b) there are people who are disposed to make systematic mistakes in computing values of functio…Read more
  •  173
    In Defense of a Non-Causal Account of Reasons Explanations
    The Journal of Ethics 12 (3-4). 2008.
    This paper defends my claim in earlier work that certain non-causal conditions are sufficient for the truth of some reasons explanations of actions, against the critique of this claim given by Randolph Clarke in his book, Libertarian Accounts of Free Will
  •  150
    Can the will be caused?
    Philosophical Review 71 (January): 49-55. 1962.
  •  140
    On Mele and Robb’s Indeterministic Frankfurt-Style Case
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 80 (2): 440-446. 2010.
    Alfred Mele and David Robb (1998, 2003) offer what they claim is a counter-example to the principle of alternative possibilities (PAP), the principle that a person is morally responsible for what he has done only if he could have done otherwise. In their example, a person makes a decision by his own indeterministic causal process though antecedent circumstances ensure he could not have done otherwise. Specifically, a simultaneously occurring process in him would deterministically cause the decis…Read more
  •  131
    Working with Fischer and Ravizza’s Account of Moral Responsibility
    The Journal of Ethics 10 (3): 229-253. 2006.
    This paper examines the account of guidance control given in Fischer and Ravizza's book, Responsibility and Control, with the aim of revising it so as to make it a better account of what needs to be added to having alternatives open to yield a specification of the control condition for responsibility that will be acceptable to an adherent of the principle that one is responsible for something only if one could have avoided it
  •  112
    Book Review. Living Without Free Will. Derk Pereboom (review)
    The Journal of Ethics 6 (3): 305-309. 2002.
  •  104
    In defense of incompatibilism
    Philosophical Studies 44 (November): 391-400. 1983.
  •  88
    Comments on Plantinga’s two-volume work on warrant
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 55 (2): 403-408. 1995.
  •  88
    Reasons Explanation: Further Defense of a Non-causal Account
    The Journal of Ethics 20 (1-3): 219-228. 2016.
    If moral responsibility requires uncaused action, as I believe, and if a reasons explanation of an action must be a causal explanation, as many philosophers of action suppose, then it follows that our responsible actions are ones we do for no reason, which is preposterous. In previous work I have argued against the second premise of this deduction, claiming that the statement that a person did A in order to satisfy their desire D will be true if the person, while doing A, intended of that action…Read more
  •  71
    Infinitism is not the solution to the regress problem
    In Matthias Steup & John Turri (eds.), Contemporary Debates in Epistemology, Blackwell. pp. 140--149. 2013.
  •  69
    Contra Reliabilism
    The Monist 68 (2): 175-187. 1985.
    The reliability of a belief-producing process is a matter of how likely it is that the process will produce beliefs that are true. The term reliabilism may be used to refer to any position that makes this idea of reliability central to the explication of some important epistemic concept. I know of three such positions that appeal to some epistemologists: a reliabilist account of what makes a belief justified, a reliabilist account of what makes a true belief knowledge, and a reliabilist answer t…Read more
  •  67
  •  62
    Knowing Less by Knowing More
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 5 (1): 151-162. 1980.
  •  57
    Book Review. Teleological realism. Scott Sehon. (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 76 (3). 2008.
    No Abstract
  •  56
    Justification
    Journal of Philosophical Research 15 93-107. 1990.
    This paper argues that a fact which constitutes part of a subject’s being justified in adopting an action or a belief at a particular time need not be part of what induced the subject to adopt that action or belief but it must be something to which the subject had immediate access. It argues that similar points hold for justification of the involuntary acquisition of a belief and for the justification of continuing a belief (actively or dispositionally.)
  •  56
  •  56
    Trying to Act
    In Joseph Keim Campbell, Michael O'Rourke & David Shier (eds.), Freedom and Determinism, Mit Press. 2004.