• PhilPeople
  • PhilPapers
  • PhilArchive
  • PhilEvents
  • PhilJobs
  • Sign in
PhilPeople
 
  • Sign in
  • News Feed
  • Find Philosophers
  • Departments
  • Radar
  • Help
 

Drag to reposition

Caspar Hare
Massachusetts Institute of Technology
  •  Home
  •  Publications
    34
    • Most Recent
    • Most Downloaded
    • Topics
  •  Events
    4
  •  News and Updates
    36

 More details
  • Massachusetts Institute of Technology
    Department of Linguistics and Philosophy
    Professor
Cambridge, Massachusetts, United States of America
Areas of Interest
Metaphysics
Normative Ethics
  • All publications (34)
  •  2
    On Myself, and Other, Less Important Subjects
    Princeton University Press. 2009.
  •  7
    A Puzzle about Other-directed Time-bias 1
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 86 (2): 269-277. 2008.
    Should we be time-biased on behalf of other people? ‘Sometimes yes, sometimes no’—it is tempting to answer. But this is not right. On pain of irrationality, we cannot be too selective about when we are time-biased on behalf of other people.
  •  17
    Risk and radical uncertainty in HIV research
    Journal of Medical Ethics 43 (2): 87-89. 2017.
    Biomedical EthicsMoral Uncertainty
  •  41
    On Myself, and Other, Less Important, Subjects
    Dissertation, Princeton University. 2003.
    In this dissertation I spell out, and make a case for, egocentric presentism, a view about what it is for a thing to be me. I argue that there are benefits associated with adopting this view. ;The chief benefit comes in the sphere of ethics. Many of us, when we think about what to do, feel a particular kind of ambivalence. On the one hand we are moved by an impartial concern for the greater good. We feel the force of considerations of the form: 'all things considered, doing...will make things be…Read more
    In this dissertation I spell out, and make a case for, egocentric presentism, a view about what it is for a thing to be me. I argue that there are benefits associated with adopting this view. ;The chief benefit comes in the sphere of ethics. Many of us, when we think about what to do, feel a particular kind of ambivalence. On the one hand we are moved by an impartial concern for the greater good. We feel the force of considerations of the form: 'all things considered, doing...will make things better overall'. On the other hand we are selfish. We feel the force of considerations of the form 'doing...will make things better for me.' And it appears as if these sorts of considerations often conflict. Often by doing what makes things better for me I do not make things better overall, and vice-versa. But egocentric presentism is capable of resolving this conflict. As an egocentric presentist I can think both that considerations of the greater good always count in favor my doing what's good for me, and that considerations of the greater good always count in favor of other people doing what's good for them. ;Another benefit comes in the sphere of metaphysics. As an egocentric presentist I can make sense of some otherwise perplexing puzzles about personal identity over time, by combining a non-reductionist view about who I will be, with Parfitian reductionism about personal identity over time and a lean physicalist ontology
    Ethics
  •  3
    3 Egocentrism and Egocentric Metaphysics
    In On Myself, and Other, Less Important Subjects, Princeton University Press. pp. 19-40. 2009.
    Philosophy of Linguistics
  • 10. Laurence Thomas, The Family and the Political Self Laurence Thomas, The Family and the Political Self (pp. 580-585)
    with Richard J. Arneson, Robert E. Goodin, David Schmidtz, Agnieszka Jaworska, and Lionel K. McPherson
    In Laurie DiMauro (ed.), Ethics, Greenhaven Press. 2007.
    Social and Political Philosophy, Misc
  •  74
    The ethics of morphing
    Philosophical Studies 145 (1). 2009.
    Here's one piece of practical reasoning: "If I do this then a person will reap some benefits and suffer some costs. On balance, the benefits outweigh the costs. So I ought to do it." Here's another: "If I do this then one person will reap some benefits and another will suffer some costs. On balance, the benefits to the one person outweigh the costs to the other. So I ought to do it." Many influential philosophers say that there is something dubious about the second piece of reasoning. They say t…Read more
    Here's one piece of practical reasoning: "If I do this then a person will reap some benefits and suffer some costs. On balance, the benefits outweigh the costs. So I ought to do it." Here's another: "If I do this then one person will reap some benefits and another will suffer some costs. On balance, the benefits to the one person outweigh the costs to the other. So I ought to do it." Many influential philosophers say that there is something dubious about the second piece of reasoning. They say that it makes sense to trade-off costs and benefits within lives, but not across lives. In this paper I make a case for the second piece of reasoning. My case turns on the existence of morphing sequences—sequences of possible states of affairs across which people transform smoothly into other people
    Ethics
  •  83
    Self-Bias, Time-Bias, and the Metaphysics of Self and Time
    Journal of Philosophy 104 (7): 350-373. 2007.
    This is about the metaphysics of the self and ethical egoism. It can serve as a preview for my manuscript-in-progress below.
    Value Theory, Miscellaneous
  •  137
    Obligation and Regret When There is No Fact of the Matter About What Would Have Happened if You Had not Done What You Did
    Noûs 45 (1). 2011.
    It is natural to distinguish between objective and subjective senses of
    Usability of Consequentialism
  •  42
    Bradley , Ben . Well-Being and Death . Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009. Pp. 224. $60.00 (cloth)
    Ethics 121 (4): 797-799. 2011.
    Value TheoryValue Theory, Miscellaneous
  •  307
    Voices from Another World: Must We Respect the Interests of People Who Do Not, and Will Never, Exist?
    Ethics 117 (3): 498-523. 2007.
    This is about the rights and wrongs of bringing people into existence. In a nutshell: sometimes what matters is not what would have happened to you, but what would have happened to the person who would have been in your position, even if that person never actually exists.
    Social and Political Philosophy, Miscellaneous
  •  95
    Should We Wish Well to All?
    Philosophical Review 125 (4): 451-472. 2016.
    Some moral theories tell you, in some situations in which you are interacting with a group of people, to avoid acting in the way that is expectedly best for everybody. This essay argues that such theories are mistaken. Go ahead and do what is expectedly best for everybody. The argument is based on the thought that when interacting with an individual it is fine for you to act in the expected interests of the individual and that many interactions with individuals may compose an interaction with a …Read more
    Some moral theories tell you, in some situations in which you are interacting with a group of people, to avoid acting in the way that is expectedly best for everybody. This essay argues that such theories are mistaken. Go ahead and do what is expectedly best for everybody. The argument is based on the thought that when interacting with an individual it is fine for you to act in the expected interests of the individual and that many interactions with individuals may compose an interaction with a group.
    Philosophy of Mind, Miscellaneous
  •  75
    Rationality and the distant needy
    Philosophy and Public Affairs 35 (2). 2007.
    This is my argument for the claim that morality is very demanding indeed. In a nutshell: being consistent is harder than you think.
    Distributive JusticeRationalityEthicsGlobal Justice
  • Introduction
    In On Myself, and Other, Less Important Subjects, Princeton University Press. 2009.
  •  4
    Acknowledgments
    In On Myself, and Other, Less Important Subjects, Princeton University Press. 2009.
  •  41
    The Limits of Kindness
    Oxford University Press. 2013.
    Caspar Hare presents a bold and original approach to questions of what we ought to do, and why we ought to do it. He breaks with tradition to argue that we can tackle difficult problems in normative ethics by starting with a principle that is humble and uncontroversial. Being moral involves wanting particular other people to be better off
    Ethics
  •  4
    7 Skepticism and Humility
    In On Myself, and Other, Less Important Subjects, Princeton University Press. pp. 91-98. 2009.
  •  116
    Obligations to Merely Statistical People
    Journal of Philosophy 109 (5-6): 378-390. 2012.
    Ethics
  •  1
    Contents
    In On Myself, and Other, Less Important Subjects, Princeton University Press. 2009.
    The Contents of Perception
  •  9
    2 Time- Bias and the Metaphysics of Time
    In On Myself, and Other, Less Important Subjects, Princeton University Press. pp. 9-18. 2009.
    Aspects of Time
  •  98
    Realism About Tense and Perspective
    Philosophy Compass 5 (9): 760-769. 2010.
    On one view of time past, present and future things exist, but their being past, present or future does not consist in their standing in before‐ and after‐relations to other things. So, for example, the event of the signing of the Magna Carta is past, and its being so does not consist in, or reduce to, its coming before the events of 2010.In this paper I discuss arguments for and against this view and view in its near vicinity, perspectival realism. I suggest that perspectival realism is a bette…Read more
    On one view of time past, present and future things exist, but their being past, present or future does not consist in their standing in before‐ and after‐relations to other things. So, for example, the event of the signing of the Magna Carta is past, and its being so does not consist in, or reduce to, its coming before the events of 2010.In this paper I discuss arguments for and against this view and view in its near vicinity, perspectival realism. I suggest that perspectival realism is a better view than tense realism. It shares the principal virtues, but not the principal vices, of tense realism
    Temporal Experience, MiscTemporal Expressions
  •  5
    Index
    In On Myself, and Other, Less Important Subjects, Princeton University Press. pp. 111-114. 2009.
  •  9
    5 A Problem about Personal Identity over Time
    In On Myself, and Other, Less Important Subjects, Princeton University Press. pp. 57-72. 2009.
    Theories of Personal Identity
  •  4
    6 The Solution
    In On Myself, and Other, Less Important Subjects, Princeton University Press. pp. 73-90. 2009.
  •  128
    Self‐Reinforcing and Self‐Frustrating Decisions
    with Brian Hedden
    Noûs 50 (3): 604-628. 2016.
    Causal Decision Theory
  •  56
    Perfectly balanced interests
    Philosophical Perspectives 23 (1): 165-176. 2009.
    Ethics
  •  11
    4 Clarifications
    In On Myself, and Other, Less Important Subjects, Princeton University Press. pp. 41-56. 2009.
  •  37
    Torture – Does Timing Matter?
    Journal of Moral Philosophy 11 (4): 385-394. 2014.
    Value TheoryTorture
  •  19
    Review of Saul Smilansky, Ten Moral Paradoxes (review)
    Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2009 (5). 2009.
    Theories of Free Will
  •  4
    Notes
    In On Myself, and Other, Less Important Subjects, Princeton University Press. pp. 99-106. 2009.
  • Prev.
  • 1
  • 2
  • Next
PhilPeople logo

On this site

  • Find a philosopher
  • Find a department
  • The Radar
  • Index of professional philosophers
  • Index of departments
  • Help
  • Acknowledgments
  • Careers
  • Contact us
  • Terms and conditions

Brought to you by

  • The PhilPapers Foundation
  • The American Philosophical Association
  • Centre for Digital Philosophy, Western University
PhilPeople is currently in Beta Sponsored by the PhilPapers Foundation and the American Philosophical Association
Feedback