•  45
    Plato's Introduction of Forms (review)
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 45 (3): 485-486. 2007.
    Christine Jean Thomas - Plato's Introduction of Forms - Journal of the History of Philosophy 45:3 Journal of the History of Philosophy 45.3 485-486 Muse Search Journals This Journal Contents Reviewed by Christine J. Thomas Dartmouth College R. M. Dancy. Plato's Introduction of Forms. Cambridge-New York: Cambridge University Press, 2004. Pp. xii + 348. Cloth, $75.00. Russell Dancy's recent book could easily bear the title, 'A Socratic Theory of Definition'. The first two-thirds of the text extrac…Read more
  •  40
    The case of the etymologies in Plato's cratylus
    Philosophy Compass 2 (2). 2007.
    The Cratylus contains Plato's most extensive study of the relation of language to reality and to the pursuit of wisdom. Yet the dialogue has remained relatively neglected in efforts to understand Plato's deepest metaphysical and epistemological commitments. The blame for such neglect lies largely in the dialogue's extensive, difficult, even mysterious etymological section. Recent attempts to make sense of the bulk of the Cratylus are shedding much welcome light on the important roles that the et…Read more
  •  138
    Socratic Wisdom: The Model of Knowledge in Plato’s Early Dialogues
    Philosophical Review 110 (4): 590-593. 2001.
    Socrates expresses at least some interest in the knowledge of knowledge as an ability “to divide things and say that one is knowledge and the other is not knowledge”. If Hugh Benson’s characteristically lucid and careful book succeeds in its portrayal of Socrates as epistemologist, then the Charmides text is perhaps more optimistic than is often conceded. For unlike Gregory Vlastos’s Socrates, who was “no epistemologist, ” Benson’s promises “a philosophically complex, fundamentally coherent, and…Read more
  •  24
    Socratic Wisdom (review)
    Philosophical Review 110 (4): 590-593. 2001.
    Socrates expresses at least some interest in the knowledge of knowledge as an ability “to divide things and say that one is knowledge and the other is not knowledge”. If Hugh Benson’s characteristically lucid and careful book succeeds in its portrayal of Socrates as epistemologist, then the Charmides text is perhaps more optimistic than is often conceded. For unlike Gregory Vlastos’s Socrates, who was “no epistemologist, ” Benson’s promises “a philosophically complex, fundamentally coherent, and…Read more
  •  121
    Speaking of Something: Plato’s Sophist and Plato’s Beard
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 38 (4). 2008.
    The Eleatic Visitor speaks forcefully when he insists, ‘Necessarily, whenever there is speech, it is speech of something; it is impossible for it not to be of something’. For ‘if it were not of anything, it would not be speech at all; for we showed that it is impossible for there to be speech that is speech of nothing’. Presumably, at 263c10, when he claims to have ‘shown’ that it is impossible for speech to be of nothing, the Visitor is referring back to the Parmenidean puzzles at Sophist 237ff…Read more
  •  30
    Plato's Prometheanism
    In David Sedley (ed.), Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy Xxxi: Winter 2006, Oxford University Press. pp. 31--203. 2006.
  • Plato's Prometheanism
    Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 31 203-231. 2006.
  •  72
    Plato on Metaphysical Explanation: Does 'Participating' Mean Nothing?
    Studia Philosophica Estonica 7 (2): 168. 2014.
    According to Aristotle, Plato's efforts at metaphysical explanation not only fail, they are nonsensical. In particular, Plato's appeals to Forms as metaphysically explanatory of the sensibles that participate in them is "empty talk" since "'participating' means nothing". I defend Plato against Aristotle's charge by identifying a particular, substantive model of metaphysical predication as the favored model of Plato's late ontology. The model posits two basic metaphysical predication relations: s…Read more
  •  1
    In this dissertation I explore Plato's views about the nature of language and thought, and their relations to the world. Plato is sometimes thought to hold that meaningful terms do not require referents at all. Others argue that he holds a referential theory of meaning according to which the meaning of a term just is its referent. I reject both of these views, arguing that Plato thinks that a significant term must have a referent but that the referent of a term does not exhaust its signification…Read more
  •  85
    Inquiry without names in Plato's cratylus
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 46 (3). 2008.
    The interlocutors of Plato’s Cratylus agree that “it is far better to learn and to inquire from the things themselves than from their names”. Although surprisingly little attention has been paid to these remarks, at least some commentators view Plato as articulating a preference for direct, nonlinguistic cognitive access to the objects of inquiry. Another commentator takes Plato simply to recommend first-hand, yet linguistic, experience in addition to instruction from experts. This paper defends…Read more
  •  31
    False Beliefand the Meno Paradox (review)
    International Studies in Philosophy 36 (1): 249-250. 2004.
  •  29
    Colloquium 2: Plato on the Nature of Life Itself
    Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 18 (1): 39-73. 2003.