•  1064
    Linguistic practice and false-belief tasks
    Mind and Language 25 (3): 298-328. 2010.
    Jill de Villiers has argued that children's mastery of sentential complements plays a crucial role in enabling them to succeed at false-belief tasks. Josef Perner has disputed that and has argued that mastery of false-belief tasks requires an understanding of the multiplicity of perspectives. This paper attempts to resolve the debate by explicating attributions of desires and beliefs as extensions of the linguistic practices of making commands and assertions, respectively. In terms of these ling…Read more
  • Do perceptions justify beliefs? : the argument from "looks" talk
    In Johan Gersel, Rasmus Thybo Jensen, Morten S. Thaning & Søren Overgaard (eds.), In the light of experience: new essays on perception and reasons, Oxford University Press. 2018.
  •  27
    Paradoxes of truth-in-context-X
    Philosophical Studies 180 (5-6): 1467-1489. 2021.
    We may suppose that the truth predicate that we utilize in our semantic metalanguage is a two-place predicate relating sentences to contexts, the truth-in-context-X predicate. Seeming paradoxes pertaining to the truth-in-context-X predicate can be blocked by placing restrictions on the structure of contexts. While contexts must specify a domain of contexts, and what a context constant denotes relative to a context must be a context in the context domain of that context, no context may belong to …Read more
  •  71
    Imagination constrained, imagination constructed
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 67 (1): 485-512. 2024.
    A number of authors have asked what it takes for a course of mental imagery to be epistemically or practically useful. This paper addresses a prior question, namely, the difference between courses of imagination that are realistic and those that are fantastic. One approach, suggested by recent literature concerning the utility of imagery, holds that a course of imagination represents realistically if and only if the course of events represented conforms to certain accepted constraints. Against t…Read more
  • Scientific Realism as an Issue in Semantics
    In Patrick Greenough & Michael P. Lynch (eds.), Truth and Realism, Clarendon Press. 2006.
  •  40
    A strictly stronger relative must
    Thought: A Journal of Philosophy 10 (2): 82-89. 2021.
    It is widely accepted that when ‘might’ expresses certain kinds of relative modality, the sentence ‘p and it might not be the case that p’ is in some sense inconsistent. It has proven difficult to define a formal semantics that explicates this inconsistency while meeting certain other desiderata, in particular, that p does not imply ‘Must p’. This paper presents such a semantics. The key idea is that background contexts have to have multiple levels, including an inner set consisting of worlds…Read more
  •  140
    Inner Speech as the Internalization of Outer Speech
    In Peter Langland-Hassan & Agustín Vicente (eds.), Inner Speech: New Voices, Oxford University Press. pp. 53-77. 2018.
    This paper aims to clear a path for the thesis that inner speech, in the very languages we speak, is the sole medium of all conceptual thought. First, it is argued that inner speech should not be identified with the auditory imagery of speech. Since they are distinct, there may be many more episodes of inner speech than those that are accompanied by auditory imagery. Second, it is argued that it is not necessary to conceive of linguistic communication as a matter of the speaker’s revealing th…Read more
  •  69
    Belief Attribution as Indirect Communication
    In Ladislav Koreň, Hans Bernhard Schmid, Preston Stovall & Leo Townsend (eds.), Groups, Norms and Practices: Essays on Inferentialism and Collective Intentionality, Springer. pp. 173-187. 2021.
    This paper disputes the widespread assumption that beliefs and desires may be attributed as theoretical entities in the service of the explanation and predic- tion of human behavior. The literature contains no clear account of how beliefs and desires might generate actions, and there is good reason to deny that principles of rationality generate a choice on the basis of an agent’s beliefs and desires. An alter- native conception of beliefs and desires is here introduced, according to which an at…Read more
  •  44
    Indicative Conditionals in Objective Contexts
    Theoria 86 (5): 651-687. 2020.
    A conversation can be conceived as aiming to circumscribe a set of possibilities that are relevant to the goals of the conversation. This set of possibilities may be conceived as determined by the goals and objective circumstances of the interlocutors and not by their propositional attitudes. An indicative conditional can be conceived as circumscribing a set of possibilities that have a certain property: If the set of relevant possibilities is subsequently restricted to one in which the antecede…Read more
  •  77
    On the Difference Between Realistic and Fantastic Imagining
    Erkenntnis 87 (4): 1563-1582. 2020.
    When we imaginatively picture what might happen, we may take what we imagine to be either realistic or fantastic. A wine glass falling to the floor and shattering is realistic. A wine glass falling and morphing into a bird and flying away is fantastic. What does the distinction consist in? Two important necessary conditions are here defined. The first is a condition on the realistic representation of spatial configuration, grounded in an account of the imagistic representation of spatial configu…Read more
  •  544
    Metacognitive deficits in categorization tasks in a population with impaired inner speech
    with Peter Langland-Hassan, Michael J. Richardson, Aimee Deitz, and Frank F. Faries
    Acta Psychologica 181 62-74. 2017.
    This study examines the relation of language use to a person’s ability to perform categorization tasks and to assess their own abilities in those categorization tasks. A silent rhyming task was used to confirm that a group of people with post-stroke aphasia (PWA) had corresponding covert language production (or “inner speech”) impairments. The performance of the PWA was then compared to that of age- and education-matched healthy controls on three kinds of categorization tasks and on metacognit…Read more
  •  105
    Against the speaker-intention theory of demonstratives
    Linguistics and Philosophy 42 (2): 109-129. 2019.
    It is commonly supposed that an utterance of a demonstrative, such as “that”, refers to a given object only if the speaker intends to refer to that object. This paper poses three challenges to this theory. First, the theory threatens to beg the question by defining the content of the speaker’s intention in terms of reference. Second, the theory makes psychologically implausible demands on the speaker. Third, the theory entails that there can be no demonstratives in thought.
  • If we say that the truth of a statement of the form “S knows that p” depends on the pertinent context, that raises the question, what determines the pertinent context? One answer would be: the speaker. Another would be: the speaker and the hearer jointly somehow. Yet a third answer would be: no one gets to decide; it is a matter of what the conversation is supposed to achieve and how the world really is, and it can happen that all of the interlocutors are mistaken about the pertinent context. In…Read more
  • Etienne Bonnot de Condillac
    In Margaret Cameron, Benjamin Hill & Robert J. Stainton (eds.), Sourcebook in the History of Philosophy of Language, Springer. pp. 773-774. 2016.
    This is a brief summary of Condillac's philosophy of language in his Origins of Human Knowledge.
  •  36
    The Problem of Context-relativity in Semantics
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 93 (3): 329-333. 2016.
    This is an introduction to a special issue of Grazer Philosophische Studien on context-relativity in semantics.
  •  1
    Visual Imagery in the Thought of Monkeys and Apes
    In Kristin Andrews & Jacob Beck (eds.), The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Animal Minds, Routledge. pp. 25-33. 2017.
    Explanations of animal problem-solving often represent our choices as limited to two: first, we can explain the observed behavior as a product of trained responses to sensory stimuli, or second, we can explain it as due to the animal’s possession of general rules utilizing general concepts. My objective in this essay is to bring to life a third alternative, namely, an explanation in terms of imagistic cognition.The theory of imagistic cognition posits representations that locate objects in a mul…Read more
  •  1
    Grounding Assertion and Acceptance in Mental Imagery
    In Ondřej Beran, Vojtěch Kolman & Ladislav Koreň (eds.), From rules to meanings. New essays on inferentialism, Routledge. pp. 49-62. 2018.
    How can thinking be effective in enabling us to meet our goals? If we answer this in terms of representation relations between thoughts and the world, then we are challenged to explain what representation is, which no one has been able to do. If we drop the appeal to representation, then it is hard to explain why certain inferences are good and others are not. This paper outlines a strategy for a nonrepresentationalist account of the way in which the structure of reality may drive cognition. …Read more
  •  66
    Open Texture and Schematicity as Arguments for Non-referential Semantics
    In Klaus Petrus Sarah-Jane Conrad (ed.), Meaning, Context, and Methodology, Mouton De Gruyter. pp. 13-30. 2017.
    Many of the terms of our language, such as “jar”, are open-textured in the sense that their applicability to novel objects is not entirely determined by their past usage. Many others, such as the verbs “use” and “have”, are schematic in the sense that they have only a very general meaning although on any particular occasion of use they denote some more particular relation. The phenomena of open texture and schematicity constitute a sharp challenge to referential semantics, which assumes that e…Read more
  •  12
    On the Evidence for Prelinguistic Concepts
    Theoria 20 (3): 287-297. 2010.
    Language acquisition is often said to be a process of mapping words into pre-existing concepts. If that is right, then we ought to be able to obtain experimental evidence for the existence of concepts in prelinguistic children, as intended in the work of Paul Quinn. This paper argues that Quinn's results have an alternative explanation.
  •  74
    Three Kinds of Nonconceptual Seeing-as
    Review of Philosophy and Psychology 8 (4): 763-779. 2017.
    It is commonly supposed that perceptual representations in some way embed concepts and that this embedding accounts for the phenomenon of seeing-as. But there are good reasons, which will be reviewed here, to doubt that perceptions embed concepts. The alternative is to suppose that perceptions are marks in a perceptual similarity space that map into locations in an objective quality space. From this point of view, there are at least three sorts of seeing-as. First, in cases of ambiguity resoluti…Read more
  • The Refutation of Internalism: An Essay on Intentionality
    Dissertation, University of Pittsburgh. 1984.
    "Internalism" is the thesis that a subject's internal physical structure determines which beliefs and desires are properly attributable to him. Internalist theories of intentionality purport to solve several philosophical problems, most notably, how explanation in terms of belief and desire is compatible with subsumption of the subject under physical law. This dissertation argues that internalism is false. First it is argued that an internalistic construal of belief would make it impossible to u…Read more
  •  107
    Do Perceptions Justify Beliefs? The Argument from "Looks" Talk
    In Gersel Johan, Thybo Jensen Rasmus, Thaning M. & Overgaard S. (eds.), In Light of Experience: Essays on Reason and Perception, Oxford University Press. pp. 141-160. 2018.
    Why should we believe that perceptions justify beliefs? One argument starts with the premise that sentences of the form “a looks F” may be used to justify conclusions of the form “a is F”. I will argue that this argument for the claim that perceptions justify beliefs founders on the following dilemma: Either “a looks F” does not report the content of a perception or, if it does, then it does not justify the conclusion “a is F”.
  •  66
    Language and Reality: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Language (review)
    Teaching Philosophy 10 (3): 269-271. 1987.
    A review of Devitt and Sterelny, Language and Reality (1st edition)
  •  93
    The rule of universal instantiation appears to be subject to counterexamples, although the rule of existential generalization is not subject to the same doubts. This paper is a survey of ways of responding to this problem, both conservative and revisionist. The conclusion drawn is that logical validity should be defined in terms of assertibility in a context rather than in terms of truth on an interpretation. Contexts are here defined, not in terms of the attitudes of the interlocutors, but in t…Read more
  •  132
    How many bare demonstratives are there in English?
    Linguistics and Philosophy 37 (4): 291-314. 2014.
    In order to capture our intuitions about the logical consistency of sentences and the logical validity of arguments, a semantics for a natural language has to allow for the fact that different occurrences of a single bare demonstrative, such as “this”, may refer to different objects. But it is not obvious how to formulate a semantic theory in order to achieve this result. This paper first criticizes several proposals: that we should formulate our semantics as a semantics for tokens, not expressi…Read more
  •  198
    I define T-schema deflationism as the thesis that a theory of truth for our language can simply take the form of certain instances of Tarski's schema (T). I show that any effective enumeration of these instances will yield as a dividend an effective enumeration of all truths of our language. But that contradicts Gödel's First Incompleteness Theorem. So the instances of (T) constituting the T-Schema deflationist's theory of truth are not effectively enumerable, which casts doubt on the idea that …Read more
  •  99
    Conditionals in context
    Erkenntnis 27 (3). 1987.
    This paper is obsolete. It is superseded by the book, Conditionals in Context, MIT Press, 2005.
  •  363
    Semantics and Pragmatics
    In Gillian Russell & Delia Graff Fara (eds.), Routledge Companion to the Philosophy of Language, Routledge. 2012.
    Semantics deals with the literal meaning of sentences. Pragmatics deals with what speakers mean by their utterances of sentences over and above what those sentences literally mean. However, it is not always clear where to draw the line. Natural languages contain many expressions that may be thought of both as contributing to literal meaning and as devices by which speakers signal what they mean. After characterizing the aims of semantics and pragmatics, this chapter will set out the issues conce…Read more
  •  164
    A new skeptical solution
    Acta Analytica 14 113-129. 1999.
    Kripke's puzzle about rule-following is a form of the traditional problem of the nature of linguistic meaning. A skeptical solution explains not what meaning is but the role that talk of meaning plays in the linguistic community. Contrary to what some have claimed, the skeptical approach is not self-refuting. However, Kripke's own skeptical solution is inadequate. He has not adequately explained the conditions under which we are justified in attributing meanings or the utility of the practice of…Read more