•  844
    Miranda Fricker's important study of epistemic injustice is focussed primarily on testimonial injustice and hermeneutic injustice. It explores how agents' capacities to make assertions and provide testimony can be impaired in ways that can involve forms of distinctively epistemic injustice. My paper identifies a wider range of forms of epistemic injustice that do not all involve the ability to make assertions or offer testimony. The paper considers some examples of some other ways in which injus…Read more
  •  236
    Questions, epistemology, and inquiries
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 77 (1): 1-21. 2008.
    Questions are relevant to epistemology because they formulate cognitive goals, they are used to elicit information, they are used in Socratic reflection and knowledge sentences often have indirect question complements. The paper explores what capacities we must possess if we are to understand questions and identify and evaluate potential answers to them. The later sections explore different ways in which these matters depend upon pragmatic and other contextual considerations.
  •  190
    Affective states and epistemic immediacy
    Metaphilosophy 34 (1-2): 78-96. 2003.
    Ethics studies the evaluation of actions, agents and their mental states and characters from a distinctive viewpoint or employing a distinctive vocabulary. And epistemology examines the evaluation of actions (inquiries and assertions), agents (believers and inquirers), and their states (belief and attitudes) from a different viewpoint. Given this common concern with evaluation, we should surely expect there to be considerable similarities between the issues examined and the ideas employed in the…Read more
  •  167
    Reasons for belief, reasoning, virtues
    Philosophical Studies 130 (1): 47--70. 2006.
    The paper offers an explanation of what reasons for belief are, following Paul Grice in focusing on the roles of reasons in the goal-directed activity of reasoning. Reasons are particularly salient considerations that we use as indicators of the truth of beliefs and candidates for belief. Reasons are distinguished from enabling conditions by being things that we should be able to attend to in the course of our reasoning, and in assessing how well our beliefs are supported. The final section argu…Read more
  •  142
    Conscious Belief and Deliberation
    with K. V. Wilkes
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 55 (1): 75-108. 1981.
  •  133
    Scepticism
    Routledge. 1990.
    Scepticism is a subject which has preoccupied philosophers for two thousand years. This book presents an historical perspective on scepticism by considering contrasting views, such as those of Sextus Empiricus, Descartes and Hume, on why scepticism is important. With its historical perspective and analysis of contemporary discussions, _Scepticism_ provides a broad focus on the subject, differing from other discussions of the topic in the importance it attaches to scepticism both in Greek thought…Read more
  •  123
    Doubt: Affective States and the Regulation of Inquiry
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary Volume 24 (sup1): 203-225. 1998.
    Pragmatists challenge a sharp separation of issues of theoretical and practical rationality. This can encourage a sort of anti-realism: our classifications and theories are shaped by our interests and practical concerns. However, it need not do this. A more fundamental theme is that cognition is itself an activity, the attempt to solve problems and discover truths effectively and responsibly. Evidence has to be collected, experiments have to be devised and carried out, dialogues must be engaged …Read more
  •  122
    Cognitive virtues and epistemic evaluations
    International Journal of Philosophical Studies 2 (2). 1994.
    (1994). Cognitive virtues and epistemic evaluations. International Journal of Philosophical Studies: Vol. 2, No. 2, pp. 211-227. doi: 10.1080/09672559408570791
  •  117
    Some fundamental epistemic norms govern the conduct of the activity of inquiry and the progress of theoretical deliberation. We monitor our deliberations by raising questions about how they should be conducted and about how effectively they have been carried out. Such questions ‘occur’ to us: we are often passive recipients of them. The paper discusses what determines when questions should occur to us and it investigates how far these observations can be seen as threatening our freedom of mind. …Read more
  •  117
    Fallibilism and the Aim of Inquiry
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 81 (1). 2007.
  •  117
    Two Conceptions of Moral Realism
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 60 (1). 1986.
  •  101
    Short on Peirce's early theory of signs
    Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 43 (4). 2007.
    : T.L. Short's book argues that Peirce's early theory of signs was flawed, and that the development of his mature theories required a new start and the rejection of some fundamental doctrines from the earlier view. While agreeing that Peirce's view of signs changed and agreeing on the new developments that were of most significance, I express some doubts about Short's diagnosis of why such changes were required. I argue that the changes were required, not by internal inconsistencies in the earli…Read more
  •  101
    Pragmatism
    with Cathy Legg
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2019.
    An overview of a philosophical movement originating in the United States of America in the 19th century.
  •  98
    Regulating Inquiry
    The Proceedings of the Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 5 149-157. 2000.
    Appeal to the idea of an epistemic virtue promises insight into our practices of epistemic evaluation through employing a distinctive view of the ways in which we formulate and respond to reasons. Traits of ‘epistemic character’ guide our reasoning and reflection, and can be responsible for various forms of irrationality. One component of such a view is that emotions, sentiments and other affective states are far more central to questions of epistemic rationality than is commonly supposed. This …Read more
  •  90
    Minds, Machines And Evolution (edited book)
    Cambridge University Press. 1984.
    This is a volume of original essays written by philosophers and scientists and dealing with philosophical questions arising from work in evolutionary biology and artificial intelligence. In recent years both of these areas have been the focus for attempts to provide a scientific, model of a wide range of human capacities - most prominently perhaps in sociobiology and cognitive psychology. The book therefore examines a number of issues related to the search for a 'naturalistic' or scientific acco…Read more
  •  86
    The inaugural address: Fallibilism and the aim of inquiry
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 81 (1). 2007.
  •  83
    13 Emotions and epistemic evaluations
    In Peter Carruthers, Stephen P. Stich & Michael Siegal (eds.), The Cognitive Basis of Science, Cambridge University Press. pp. 251. 2002.
  •  78
    Belief and freedom of mind
    Philosophical Explorations 12 (2). 2009.
    There are concepts of freedom of mind and freedom of belief which do not depend on the freedom of agency. After discussing some impediments to such freedom of mind, the paper explores some arguments of Dennett, Michael Smith and Philip Pettit, and Josefa Toribio. Borrowing ideas from Schiller, the paper concludes that such freedom has an emotional or aesthetic dimension
  •  77
    Peirce
    Routledge. 1985.
    This book is available either individually, or as part of the specially-priced Arguments of the Philosphers Collection.
  •  76
    Truth, rationality, and pragmatism: themes from Peirce (edited book)
    Oxford University Press. 2000.
    Christopher Hookway presents a series of studies of themes from the work of the great American philosopher and pragmatist, Charles S. Peirce (1839-1913). These themes center on the question of how we are to investigate the world rationally. Hookway shows how Peirce's ideas about this continue to play an important role in contemporary philosophy.
  •  76
    Quine: Language, Experience, and Reality
    Stanford University Press. 1988.
    Introduction Quine was born in. He studied as a graduate student at Harvard, and apart from short visits to Oxford, Paris and other centres of learning, ...
  •  75
    Robert Brandom's latest book, the product of his John Locke lectures in Oxford in 2006, is a return to the philosophy of language and is easily read as a continuation and development of the views defended in Making it Explicit . The text of the lectures is presented much as they were delivered, but it contains an ‘Afterword’ of more than 30 pages which responds to questions raised when he gave the lectures, and also when they were subsequently delivered in Prague the following year. The publishe…Read more
  •  69
    Naturalized epistemology and epistemic evaluation
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 37 (4). 1994.
    The paper explores Quine's ?naturalized epistemology?, investigating whether its adoption would prevent the description or vindication of normative standards standardly employed in regulating beliefs and inquiries. Quine's defence of naturalized epistemology rejects traditional epistemological questions rather than using psychology to answer them. Although one could persuade those sensitive to the force of traditional epistemological problems only by employing the kind of argument whose philosop…Read more
  •  68
    Unnatural Doubts
    Philosophical Quarterly 43 (172): 389. 1993.
  •  65
    Regulating Inquiry
    The Proceedings of the Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 5 149-157. 2000.
    Appeal to the idea of an epistemic virtue promises insight into our practices of epistemic evaluation through employing a distinctive view of the ways in which we formulate and respond to reasons. Traits of ‘epistemic character’ guide our reasoning and reflection, and can be responsible for various forms of irrationality. One component of such a view is that emotions, sentiments and other affective states are far more central to questions of epistemic rationality than is commonly supposed. This …Read more