•  345
    Journalism ethics: a philosophical approach (edited book)
    Oxford University Press. 2010.
    Since the introduction of radio and television news, journalism has gone through multiple transformations, but each time it has been sustained by a commitment to basic values and best practices. Journalism Ethics is a reminder, a defense and an elucidation of core journalistic values, with particular emphasis on the interplay of theory, conceptual analysis and practice. The book begins with a sophisticated model for ethical decision-making, one that connects classical theories with the central p…Read more
  •  142
    The virtue of cold-heartedness
    Philosophical Studies 138 (2). 2008.
    I defend a strong version of the Kantian claim that actions done solely from duty have moral worth by (1) considering pure cases of acting from duty, (2) showing that love and sympathy, unlike a sense of duty, can often lead us to do the wrong thing, (3) carefully distinguishing moral from non-moral virtues, and (4) by distinguishing pathological sympathy from practical sympathy. Not only is acting purely from a sense of duty superior to acting from love and sympathetic feelings, but the cold-he…Read more
  •  132
    Appreciating W. D. Ross:On Duties and Consequences
    Journal of Mass Media Ethics 18 (2): 81-97. 2003.
    In this article I describe the theoretical underpinnings of 20th-century British philosopher W. D. Ross's approach to linking deontological and teleological decision making. I attempt to fill in what Ross left on the whole unanswered, that is, how to use his duties to resolve dilemmas. A case study in journalism demonstrates how to apply the theory. I conclude with an analysis of what I take to be the strengths and weaknesses in Ross's theory.
  •  128
    An obligation to provide abortion services: what happens when physicians refuse?
    with R. D. Woods
    Journal of Medical Ethics 22 (2): 115-120. 1996.
    Access to abortion services in the United States continues to decline. It does so not because of significant changes in legislation or court rulings but because fewer and fewer physicians wish to perform abortions and because most states now have "conscientious objection" legislation that makes it easy for physicians to refuse to do so. We argue in this paper that physicians have an obligation to perform all socially sanctioned medical services, including abortions, and thus that the burden of j…Read more
  •  104
    Defending Moral Realism from Empirical Evidence of Disagreement
    Social Theory and Practice 39 (3): 373-396. 2013.
    Recently, empirically minded philosophers have employed evidence of widespread, fundamental moral disagreement to argue against moral realism. I argue that the empirical evidence does not refute realism because the disagreement is consistent with certain pluralistic versions of moral realism that posit a set of pro tanto normative principles. Others have appealed to pluralism in defense of moral realism but have used pluralism to attack the empirically based approach to ethical theory. Although …Read more
  •  100
    Managed care and ethical conflicts: anything new?
    Journal of Medical Ethics 25 (5): 382-387. 1999.
    Does managed care represent the death knell for the ethical provision of medical care? Much of the current literature suggests as much. In this essay I argue that the types of ethical conflicts brought on by managed care are, in fact, similar to those long faced by physicians and by other professionals. Managed care presents new, but not fundamentally different, factors to be considered in medical decision making. I also suggest ways of better understanding and resolving these conflicts, in part…Read more
  •  86
    Nature, Virtue, and the Nature of Virtue
    Southwest Philosophy Review 26 (1): 109-117. 2010.
    Most of the philosophical work written on environmental issues focuses on notions such as rights, consequences, duties, etc. And most of the theoretical philosophy done in environmental ethics focuses on questions of whether animals, plants, or ecosystems have inherent value or moral standing independently of their usefulness to humans. A character-based approach has been largely neglected (despite a few important works). In this paper, I consider what a plausible environmental virtue ethics wou…Read more
  •  79
    Reappreciating W. D. Ross: Naturalizing Prima Facie Duties and a Proposed Method
    Journal of Mass Media Ethics 26 (4): 316-331. 2011.
    The goal of this article is to try to resolve two key problems in the duty-based approach of W. D. Ross: the source of principles and a process for moving from prima facie to actual duty. I use a naturalistic explanation for the former and a nine-step method for making concrete ethical decisions as they could be applied to journalism. Consistent with Ross's position, the process is complicated, particularly in tougher problems, and it cannot guarantee correct choices. Again consistent with Ross,…Read more
  •  69
    In deriving his moral code, Hobbes does not appeal to any mind-independent good, natural human telos, or innate human sympathies. Instead he assumes a subjectivist theory of value and an egoistic theory of human motivation. Some critics, however, doubt that his laws of nature can be constructed from such scant material. Hobbes ultimately justifies the acceptance of moral laws by the fact that they promote self-preservation. But, as Hobbes himself acknowledges, not everyone prefers survival over …Read more
  •  69
    Justifying journalistic Harms: Right to know vs. interest in knowing
    Journal of Mass Media Ethics 8 (3). 1993.
    Journalists are regularly criticized for causing harm to others, such as invading privacy, printing, or airing offensive material, and so forth. Although most sensitive journalists readily acknowledge these harms, they frequently argue that the pursuit and coverage of news is nonetheless justified because it fulfills a greater moral purpose - satisfaction of the public's right to know. This article argues that although "the public s right to know" does justify some harmful journalistic behavior,…Read more
  •  69
    Objective reporting was once among the foundational norms of U.S. journalism. The emergence of alternative and economically successful partisan models exemplified by Fox News, talk radio, and a ran...
  •  61
    Institutional culture and individual behavior: Creating an ethical environment
    Science and Engineering Ethics 10 (2): 269-276. 2004.
    Much of the work in professional ethics sees ethical problems as resulting from ethical ignorance, ethical failure or evil intent. While this approach gets at real and valid concerns, it does not capture the whole story because it does not take into account the underlying professional or institutional culture in which moral decision making is imbedded. My argument in this paper is that this culture plays a powerful and sometimes determinant role in establishing the nature of the ethical debate; …Read more
  •  56
    Cognitive neuroenhancement involves the use of medical interventions to improve normal cognitive functioning such as memory, focus, concentration, or willpower. In this paper I give a Kantian argument defending the use of CNE in science, scholarly research, and creative fields. Kant’s universal law formulation of the categorical imperative shows why enhancement is morally wrong in the familiar contexts of sports or competitive games. This argument, however, does not apply to the use of CNE in hi…Read more
  •  55
    Conscientious objection? Yes, but make sure it is genuine
    with Robert D. Woods
    American Journal of Bioethics 7 (6). 2007.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  53
    Clinical ethical consultants are subject to an unavoidable conflict of interest. Their work requires that they be independent, but incentives attached to their role chip relentlessly at independence. This that they be independent, is a problem without any solution, but it can at least be ameliorated through careful management.
  •  53
    Power, Ethics, and Journalism: Toward an Integrative Approach
    with Peggy Bowers and Anantha Babbili
    Journal of Mass Media Ethics 19 (3-4): 223-246. 2004.
    Although we think 1 of the basic purposes of journalism is to provide information vital to enhancing citizen autonomy, we also see this goal as being in direct tension with the power news media hold and wield, power that may serve to undercut, rather than enhance, citizen autonomy. We argue that the news media are ethically constrained by proceduralism, resulting in journalists asserting power inappropriately at the individual level, and unwittingly surrendering moral authority institutionally a…Read more
  •  50
    Although autonomy is clearly still the paradigm in bioethics, there is increasing concern over its value and feasibility. In agreeing with those concerns, I argue that autonomy is not just a status, but a skill, one that must be developed and maintained. I also argue that nearly all healthcare interactions do anything but promote such decisional skills, since they rely upon assent, rather than upon genuinely autonomous consent. Thus, throughout most of their medical lives, patients are socialise…Read more
  •  43
    A Defense of the Philosopher-Ethicist as Moral Expert
    Journal of Clinical Ethics 14 (4): 259-269. 2003.
  •  40
    Deception and the Clinical Ethicist
    American Journal of Bioethics 21 (5): 4-12. 2021.
    Lying to one’s patients is wrong. So obvious as to border on a platitude, this truism is one that bioethicists have heartily endorsed for several decades. Deception, the standard line holds, underc...
  •  34
    Ethics Across the Curriculum—Pedagogical Perspectives
    with Elaine E. Englehardt, Michael S. Pritchard, Robert Baker, Michael D. Burroughs, José A. Cruz-Cruz, Randall Curren, Michael Davis, Aine Donovan, Deni Elliott, Karin D. Ellison, Challie Facemire, William J. Frey, Joseph R. Herkert, Karlana June, Robert F. Ladenson, Glen Miller, Deborah S. Mower, Lisa H. Newton, David T. Ozar, Alan A. Preti, Wade L. Robison, Brian Schrag, Alan Tomhave, Phyllis Vandenberg, Mark Vopat, Sandy Woodson, Daniel E. Wueste, and Qin Zhu
    Springer Verlag. 2018.
    Late in 1990, the Center for the Study of Ethics in the Professions at Illinois Institute of Technology (lIT) received a grant of more than $200,000 from the National Science Foundation to try a campus-wide approach to integrating professional ethics into its technical curriculum.! Enough has now been accomplished to draw some tentative conclusions. I am the grant's principal investigator. In this paper, I shall describe what we at lIT did, what we learned, and what others, especially phil…Read more
  •  33
    The Corporation, Its Members, and Moral Accountability
    Business and Professional Ethics Journal 3 (1): 33-44. 1983.
  •  31
    Creating an Effective Newspaper Ombudsman Position
    Journal of Mass Media Ethics 15 (4): 248-256. 2000.
    In this article I argue, first, that genuinely effective ombudsmen could help restore news credibility-thereby staving off other, more intrusive external intervention-and that the position must have true sanctioning authority, much like that of the ethics officer in many corporations. I also argue that the effective ombudsman will be one who sufficiently understands the workings of journalism but who is not immersed in its ethos. This distancing is necessary for genuine critical appraisal to be …Read more
  •  31
    Religious Belief and Surrogate Medical Decision Making
    Journal of Clinical Ethics 20 (2): 192-200. 2009.
  •  28
    Universals Without Absolutes: A Theory of Media Ethics
    Journal of Media Ethics 31 (4): 198-214. 2016.
    The global turn in media ethics has presented a tough challenge for traditional models of moral theory: How do we assert common moral standards while also showing respect for the values of those from outside the Western tradition? The danger lies in advocating for either extreme: reason-dependent absolutism or cultural relativism. In this paper, I reject Cliff Christian’s attempts to solve the problem and propose instead a moral theory of universal standards that are discovered via a mix of rati…Read more
  •  24
    Judgment, Accountability, and ‘Information’
    Business and Professional Ethics Journal 14 (2): 77-92. 1995.
  •  23
    Report Cards
    with Michael Davis, Lisa H. Newton, and Elliot D. Cohen
    Journal of Mass Media Ethics 19 (3-4): 161-165. 2004.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  22
    Professionalism, Not Professionals
    with Wendy N. Wyatt, Sandra L. Borden, and Edward Wasserman
    Journal of Mass Media Ethics 27 (3): 189-205. 2012.
    The proliferation of news and information sources has motivated a need to identify those providing legitimate journalism. One temptation is to go the route of such fields as medicine and law, namely to formally professionalize. This gives a clear method for determining who is a member, with an array of associated responsibilities and rewards. We argue that making such a formal move in journalism is a mistake: Journalism does not meet the traditional criteria, and its core ethos is in conflict wi…Read more