•  201
    Humiliation, dignity and self-respect
    Philosophical Psychology 13 (4). 2000.
    That an intimate connection exists between the notion of human dignity and the notion of humiliation seems to be a commonplace among philosophers, who tend to assume that humiliation should be explained in terms of (violation of) human dignity. I believe, however, that this assumption leads to an understanding of humiliation that is too "philosophical" and too detached from psychological reality. The purpose of the paper is to modify the above connection and to offer a more "down to earth" accou…Read more
  •  173
    More on the Comparative Nature of Desert: Can a Deserved Punishment Be Unjust?
    with Ronen Avraham
    Utilitas 25 (3): 316-333. 2013.
    Adam and Eve have the same record yet receive different punishments. Adam receives the punishment that they both deserve, whereas Eve receives a more lenient punishment. In this article, we explore whether a deserved-but-unequal punishment, such as what Adam receives, can be just. We do this by explicating the conceptions of retributive justice that underlie both sides of the debate. We argue that inequality in punishment is disturbing mainly because of the disrespect it often expresses towards …Read more
  •  165
  •  154
    Hypocrisy and self‐deception
    Philosophical Psychology 10 (1): 57-75. 1997.
    Hypocrites are generally regarded as morally-corrupt, cynical egoists who consciously and deliberately deceive others in order to further their own interests. The purpose of my essay is to present a different view. I argue that hypocrisy typically involves or leads to self-deception and, therefore, that real hypocrites are hard to find. One reason for this merging of hypocrisy into self-deception is that a consistent and conscious deception of society is self-defeating from the point of view of …Read more
  •  132
    Moral Luck (edited book)
    SUNY Press. 1993.
    Some luck, in a decision of Gauguin's kind, is extrinsic to his project, some intrinsic; both are necessary for success, and hence for actual justification, but only the latter relates to un- justification. If we now broaden the range of cases slightly, ...
  •  99
    Moral and epistemic luck
    Ratio 4 (2): 146-156. 1991.
  •  95
    Modesty, pride and realistic self-assessment
    Philosophical Quarterly 42 (169): 420-438. 1992.
  •  88
    Hard cases and moral dilemmas
    Law and Philosophy 15 (2). 1996.
  •  75
    Virtue Ethics: A Critical Reader (edited book)
    Edinburgh University Press. 1997.
    The central question in contemporary ethics is whether virtue can replace duty as the primary notion in ethical theory. The subject of intense contemporary debate in ethical theory, virtue ethics is currently enjoying an increase in interest. This is the first book to focus directly on the subject. It provides a clear, systematic introduction to the area and houses under one cover a collection of the central articles published on the debate over the past decade. The essays encompass a wide range…Read more
  •  74
    The purpose of this paper is to explore the relation between the right to self-defense against an innocent attacker and the notion of moral luck. It argues that those who accept the existence of such a right rely on the assumption that mere agency makes a significant moral difference – which is precisely the assumption that underlies the view held by believers in moral luck. Those who believe in the right to self-defense against innocent attackers are thus committed to the idea of moral luck muc…Read more
  •  67
    Targeted Killing
    Theoretical Inquiries in Law 5 (1): 179-198. 2004.
    The purpose of this paper is to provide a philosophical defense for targeted killings in the wars against terror. The paper argues that if one accepts the moral legitimacy of the large-scale killing of combatants in conventional wars, one cannot object - on moral grounds - to the targeted killing of terrorists in wars against terror. If one rejects this legitimacy, one must object to all killing in war, targeted and non-targeted alike, and thus not support the view, which is criticized here, tha…Read more
  •  64
    Can Wars Be Fought Justly? The Necessity Condition Put to the Test
    Journal of Moral Philosophy 8 (3): 435-451. 2011.
    According to a widespread view, the same constraints that limit the use of otherwise immoral measures in individual self-defense apply to collective self-defense too. I try to show that this view has radical implications at the level of jus in bello, implications which have not been fully appreciated. In particular, if the necessity condition must be satisfied in all cases of killing in war, then most fighting would turn out to be unjust. One way to avoid this result is to adopt a contractualist…Read more
  •  63
    Divine Command Morality and Jewish Tradition
    with Avi Sagi
    Journal of Religious Ethics 23 (1). 1995.
    Given the religious appeal of divine command theories of morality (DCM), and given that these theories are found in both Christianity and Islam, we could expect DCM to be represented in Judaism, too. In this essay, however, we show that hardly any echoes of support for this thesis can be found in Jewish texts. We analyze texts that appear to support DCM and show they do not. We then present a number of sources clearly opposed to DCM. Finally, we offer a theory to explain the absence of DCM in Ju…Read more
  •  57
    Who Needs Imperfect Duties?
    American Philosophical Quarterly 33 (2). 1996.
  •  56
    On the Success Condition for Legitimate Self‐Defense
    Ethics 118 (4): 659-686. 2008.
    The paper discusses a neglected condition for justified self-defense, namely, 'The Success Condition [SC].' According to SC, otherwise immoral acts can be justified under the right to self-defense only if they actually achieve the intended defense from the perceived threat. If they don't, they are almost always excused, but not morally justified. I show that SC leads to a troubling puzzle because victims who estimate they cannot prevent the attack against them would be morally required to surren…Read more
  •  56
    The time to punish and the problem of moral luck
    Journal of Applied Philosophy 14 (2). 1997.
    Christopher New recently argued for the seemingly paradoxical idea that there is no moral reason not to punish someone before she commits her crime (‘prepunishment’), provided that we can be sure that she will, in fact, commit the crime in the future. I argue that the air of paradox dissolves if we understand the possibility of prepunishment as relying on an anti‐moral‐luck position. However, New does not draw the full conclusions from such a position, which would allow prepunishment even prior …Read more
  •  53
    The topic of standing to blame has recently received a lot of attention. Until now, however, it has focused mainly on the blamer's perspective, investigating what it means to say of blamers that they lose standing to blame and why it is that they lose this standing under specified conditions. The present paper focuses on the perspective of the blamees and tries to explain why they are allowed to disregard standingless, more specifically hypocritical, blame. According to the solution proposed by …Read more
  •  51
    Doors, Keys, and Moral Luck: A Reply to Domsky
    Journal of Philosophy 102 (8). 2005.
  •  47
    Moral tragedies, supreme emergencies and national-defence
    Journal of Applied Philosophy 23 (3). 2006.
    abstract Assume that some group, A, is under a serious threat from some other group, B. The only way group A can defend itself is by using lethal force against group B, but the standard conditions for using force in self‐defence are not met. Ought group A to avoid the use of force even if this means yielding to an aggressive, evil power? Most people would resist this conclusion, yet given the violation of essential conditions for self‐defence, this resistance is hard to justify. The aim of this …Read more
  •  46
    Pascal’s wager faces serious criticisms and is generally considered unconvincing. We argue that it can make a comeback powered by an unlikely ally: postmodernism. If one denies the existence of objective facts (e.g. about God or His relation to the world), then various non-theological considerations should come to the fore when considering the rationality of religious commitment and the choice of education for one’s children. In fact, we shall argue that, if one genuinely cares about one’s child…Read more
  •  46
    The debate over the so-called reality of moral dilemmas
    Philosophical Papers 19 (3): 191-211. 1990.
    No abstract
  •  40
    The Right to Parenthood
    Ethical Perspectives 10 (3): 224-235. 2003.
    The paper argues for two kinds of limitations on the right to parenthood. First, it claims that the right to parenthood does not entail a right to have as many children as one desires. This conclusion follows from the standard justifications for the right to parenthood, none of which establishes the need to grant special protection to having as many children as one desires. Second, with respect to the right to receive assistance from the state in IVF, it is suggested that the state should also b…Read more
  •  38
    Cruelty, Sadism, and the Joy of Inflicting Pain for its Own Sake
    Journal of Philosophical Research 47 23-42. 2022.
    The paper offers a theory of cruelty that includes the following claims: First, cruelty is best understood as a disposition to take delight in the very infliction of suffering on others. Thus understood, cruelty is the same phenomenon as that studied and operationalized by psychologists in the last decade or so under the heading of everyday sadism. Second, for people to be cruel, they need not have proper understanding of the moral standing of their victims. Third, ascriptions of cruelty do not …Read more
  •  38
    Fabre’s Crusade for Justice: Why We Should Not Join (review)
    Law and Philosophy 33 (3): 337-360. 2014.
    Cosmopolitan War is characterized by a tension between moral demandingness and moral permissiveness. On the one hand, Fabre is strongly committed to the value of each and all human beings as precious individuals whose value does not depend on their national or other affiliation. This commitment leads to serious constraints on what may be done to others in both individual and national self-defense. Yet the book is also unambiguously permissive. It opens the gate to far more wars than traditional …Read more
  •  38
    Doing Without Mercy
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 32 (3): 331-354. 1994.
  •  37
    Against Moral Taint
    with Yitzhak Benbaji
    Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 24 (1): 5-18. 2020.
    One motivation for adopting a justice-based view of the right to self-defense is that it seems to solve the puzzle of how a victim may kill her attacker even when doing so is not predicted to protect her from the threat imposed upon her. The paper shows (a) that this view leads to unacceptable results and (b) that its solution to cases of futile self-defense is unsatisfactory. This failure makes the interest-based theory of self-defense look more attractive, both in the context of futile self-de…Read more
  •  35
    Debunking, Vindication, and Moral Luck
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 43 (1): 203-223. 2019.
    Midwest Studies In Philosophy, EarlyView.
  •  34
    Moral Demands, Moral Pragmatics, and Being Good
    with Ariel Meirav, Meshi Ori, and Avital Pilpel
    Utilitas 22 (3). 2010.