Holborn, England, United Kingdom of Great Britain and Northern Ireland
Areas of Specialization
Science, Logic, and Mathematics
  •  437
    On the logic of theory change: Partial meet contraction and revision functions
    with Carlos E. Alchourrón and Peter Gärdenfors
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 50 (2): 510-530. 1985.
    This paper extends earlier work by its authors on formal aspects of the processes of contracting a theory to eliminate a proposition and revising a theory to introduce a proposition. In the course of the earlier work, Gardenfors developed general postulates of a more or less equational nature for such processes, whilst Alchourron and Makinson studied the particular case of contraction functions that are maximal, in the sense of yielding a maximal subset of the theory (or alternatively, of one of…Read more
  •  294
    Input/output logics
    with Leendert van der Torre
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 29 (4): 383-408. 2000.
    In a range of contexts, one comes across processes resembling inference, but where input propositions are not in general included among outputs, and the operation is not in any way reversible. Examples arise in contexts of conditional obligations, goals, ideals, preferences, actions, and beliefs. Our purpose is to develop a theory of such input/output operations. Four are singled out: simple-minded, basic (making intelligent use of disjunctive inputs), simple-minded reusable (in which outputs ma…Read more
  •  256
    A normal modal calculus between T and s4 without the finite model property
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 34 (1): 35-38. 1969.
    The first example of an intuitively meaningful propositional logic without the finite model property, and still the simplest one in the literature. The question of its decidability appears still to be open.
  •  210
    We reflect on lessons that the lottery and preface paradoxes provide for the logic of uncertain inference. One of these lessons is the unreliability of the rule of conjunction of conclusions in such contexts, whether the inferences are probabilistic or qualitative; this leads us to an examination of consequence relations without that rule, the study of other rules that may nevertheless be satisfied in its absence, and a partial rehabilitation of conjunction as a ‘lossy’ rule. A second lesson is …Read more
  •  150
    We chart the ways in which closure properties of consequence relations for uncertain inference take on different forms according to whether the relations are generated in a quantitative or a qualitative manner. Among the main themes are: the identification of watershed conditions between probabilistically and qualitatively sound rules; failsafe and classicality transforms of qualitatively sound rules; non-Horn conditions satisfied by probabilistic consequence; representation and completeness pro…Read more
  •  136
    Intuitionistic Logic and Elementary Rules
    Mind 120 (480): 1035-1051. 2011.
    The interplay of introduction and elimination rules for propositional connectives is often seen as suggesting a distinguished role for intuitionistic logic. We prove three formal results concerning intuitionistic propositional logic that bear on that perspective, and discuss their significance. First, for a range of connectives including both negation and the falsum, there are no classically or intuitionistically correct introduction rules. Second, irrespective of the choice of negation or the f…Read more
  •  121
    A study in the logic of theory change, examining the properties of maxichoice contraction and revision operations.
  •  105
    Conditional Probability in the Light of Qualitative Belief Change
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 40 (2). 2011.
    We explore ways in which purely qualitative belief change in the AGM tradition throws light on options in the treatment of conditional probability. First, by helping see why it can be useful to go beyond the ratio rule defining conditional from one-place probability. Second, by clarifying what is at stake in different ways of doing that. Third, by suggesting novel forms of conditional probability corresponding to familiar variants of qualitative belief change, and conversely. Likewise, we explai…Read more
  •  89
    Constraints for Input/Output Logics
    with Leendert van der Torre
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 30 (2). 2001.
    In a previous paper we developed a general theory of input/output logics. These are operations resembling inference, but where inputs need not be included among outputs, and outputs need not be reusable as inputs. In the present paper we study what happens when they are constrained to render output consistent with input. This is of interest for deontic logic, where it provides a manner of handling contrary-to-duty obligations. Our procedure is to constrain the set of generators of the input/outp…Read more
  •  83
    Maps between some different kinds of contraction function: The finite case
    with Carlos E. Alchourrón
    Studia Logica 45 (2). 1986.
    In some recent papers, the authors and Peter Gärdenfors have defined and studied two different kinds of formal operation, conceived as possible representations of the intuitive process of contracting a theory to eliminate a proposition. These are partial meet contraction (including as limiting cases full meet contraction and maxichoice contraction) and safe contraction. It is known, via the representation theorem for the former, that every safe contraction operation over a theory is a partial me…Read more
  •  80
    Permission from an Input/Output Perspective
    with Leendert van der Torre
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 32 (4). 2003.
    Input/output logics are abstract structures designed to represent conditional obligations and goals. In this paper we use them to study conditional permission. This perspective provides a clear separation of the familiar notion of negative permission from the more elusive one of positive permission. Moreover, it reveals that there are at least two kinds of positive permission. Although indistinguishable in the unconditional case, they are quite different in conditional contexts. One of them, whi…Read more
  •  73
    On the logic of theory change: Safe contraction
    with Carlos E. Alchourrón
    Studia Logica 44 (4). 1985.
    This paper is concerned with formal aspects of the logic of theory change, and in particular with the process of shrinking or contracting a theory to eliminate a proposition. It continues work in the area by the authors and Peter Gärdenfors. The paper defines a notion of safe contraction of a set of propositions, shows that it satisfies the Gärdenfors postulates for contraction and thus can be represented as a partial meet contraction, and studies its properties both in general and under various…Read more
  •  73
    The relationship between KLM and MAK models for nonmonotonic inference operations
    with Jürgen Dix
    Journal of Logic, Language and Information 1 (2): 131-140. 1992.
    The purpose of this note is to make quite clear the relationship between two variants of the general notion of a preferential model for nonmonotonic inference: the models of Kraus, Lehmann and Magidor (KLM models) and those of Makinson (MAK models).On the one hand, we introduce the notion of the core of a KLM model, which suffices to fully determine the associated nonmonotonic inference relation. On the other hand, we slightly amplify MAK models with a monotonic consequence operation as addition…Read more
  •  72
    Five faces of minimality
    Studia Logica 52 (3). 1993.
    We discuss similarities and residual differences, within the general semantic framework of minimality, between defeasible inference, belief revision, counterfactual conditionals, updating — and also conditional obligation in deontic logic. Our purpose is not to establish new results, but to bring together existing material to form a clear overall picture.
  •  68
    Respecting relevance in belief change
    with George Kourousias
    Análisis Filosófico 26 (1): 53-61. 2006.
    In this paper dedicated to Carlos Alchourrón, we review an issue that emerged only after his death in 1996, but would have been of great interest to him: To what extent do the formal operations of AGM belief change respect criteria of relevance? A natural criterion was proposed in 1999 by Rohit Parikh, who observed that the AGM model does not always respect it. We discuss the pros and cons of this criterion, and explain how the AGM account may be refined, if we so desire, so that it is always re…Read more
  •  64
    The paper surveys some recent work on formal aspects of the logic of theory change. It begins with a general discussion of the intuitive processes of contraction and revision of a theory, and of differing strategies for their formal study. Specific work is then described, notably Gärdenfors' postulates for contraction and revision, maxichoice contraction and revision functions and the condition of orderliness, partial meet contraction and revision functions and the condition of relationality, an…Read more
  •  62
    The paper surveys some recent work on formal aspects of the logic of theory change. It begins with a general discussion of the intuitive processes of contraction and revision of a theory, and of differing strategies for their formal study. Specific work is then described, notably Gärdenfors'' postulates for contraction and revision, maxichoice contraction and revision functions and the condition of orderliness, partial meet contraction and revision functions and the condition of relationality, a…Read more
  •  61
    On the formal representation of rights relations
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 15 (4). 1986.
    A discussion of work formalising Hohfeld's classic taxonomy of rights relations between two parties.
  •  61
    Separates the purely combinatorial component of Arrow's impossibility theorem in the theory of collective preference from its decision-theoretic part, and likewise for the closely related Blair/Bordes/Kelly/Suzumura theorem. Such a separation provides a particularly elegant proof of Arrow's result, via a new 'splitting theorem'.
  •  60
    Hierarchies of regulations and their logic
    with Carlos E. Alchourrón
    In Risto Hilpinen (ed.), New Studies in Deontic Logic: Norms, Actions, and the Foundations of Ethics, Wiley-blackwell. pp. 125--148. 1981.
    Investigates the resolution of contradictions and ambiguous derogations in a code, by means of the imposition of partial orderings.
  •  56
    Parallel interpolation, splitting, and relevance in belief change
    with George Kourousias
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 72 (3): 994-1002. 2007.
    The splitting theorem says that any set of formulae has a finest representation as a family of letter-disjoint sets. Parikh formulated this for classical propositional logic, proved it in the finite case, used it to formulate a criterion for relevance in belief change, and showed that AGMpartial meet revision can fail the criterion. In this paper we make three further contributions. We begin by establishing a new version of the well-known interpolation theorem, which we call parallel interpolati…Read more
  •  55
    On an inferential semantics for classical logic
    Logic Journal of the IGPL 22 (1): 147-154. 2014.
    We seek a better understanding of why an inferential semantics devised by Tor Sandqvist yields full classical logic, by providing and analysing a direct proof via a suitable maximality construction
  •  53
    Screened Revision
    Theoria 63 (1-2): 14-23. 1997.
    Develops a concept of revision, akin in spirit to AGM partial meet revision, but in which the postulate of 'success' may fail. The basic idea is to see such an operation as composite, with a pre-processor using a priori considerations to resolve the question of whether to revise, following which another operation revises in a manner that protects the a priori material.
  •  53
    Completeness theorems, representation theorems: what's the difference?
    Hommage À Wlodek: Philosophical Papers Dedicated to Wlodek Rabinowicz, Ed. Rønnow-Rasmussen Et Al. 2007
    A discussion of the connections and differences between completeness and representation theorems in logic, with examples drawn from classical and modal logic, the logic of friendliness, and nonmonotonic reasoning.
  •  51
    Post Completeness and Ultrafilters
    Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 20 (25-27): 385-388. 1974.
    A cardinality result in modal propositional logic.
  •  45
    Frege’s Ontological Diagram Completed
    Logica Universalis 16 (3): 381-387. 2022.
    In a letter of 1891, Frege drew a diagram to illustrate his logical ontology. We observe that it omits features that play an important role in his thought on the matter, propose an extension of the diagram to include them, and compare with a diagram of the ontology of current first-order logic.
  •  44
    How meaningful are modal operators?
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 44 (3). 1966.
    A philosophical discussion of the intuitive meaning of the formalism of modal propositional logics.
  •  42
    The concept of relevance between classical propositional formulae, defined in terms of letter-sharing, has been around for a very long time. But it began to take on a fresh life in 1999 when it was reconsidered in the context of the logic of belief change. Two new ideas appeared in independent work of Odinaldo Rodrigues and Rohit Parikh. First, the relation of relevance was considered modulo the belief set under consideration, Second, the belief set was put in a canonical form, known as its fine…Read more
  •  42
    A warning about the choice of primitive operators in modal logic
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 2 (2). 1973.
    Draws attention to some unexpected consequences of using a zero-ary connective in modal propositional logic.
  •  41
    Stenius' approach to disjunctive permission
    Theoria 50 (2-3): 138-147. 1984.
    A critical review of Stenius' account of the logic of disjunctive permissions, leading to a proposal for a closely related approach in terms of "checklist conditionals"