• Why Justification Matters
    In , . pp. 224-244. 2015.
  •  340
    Affective Consciousness and Moral Status
    Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Mind. forthcoming.
    Which beings have moral status? This paper argues that moral status requires some capacity for affective consciousness. David Chalmers rejects this view on the grounds that it denies moral status to Vulcans – namely, conscious creatures with no capacity for affective consciousness. On his more inclusive view, all conscious beings have moral status. Although we agree that consciousness is required for moral status, we disagree about how to explain this. I argue that we cannot explain why unconsci…Read more
  •  197
    Inference Without the Taking Condition
    In Kevin McCain, Scott Stapleford & Matthias Steup (eds.), Seemings: New Arguments, New Angles, Routledge. pp. 130-146. 2023.
    What is involved in making an inference? This chapter argues against what Paul Boghossian calls the Taking Condition: "Inferring necessarily involves the thinker taking his premises to support his conclusion and drawing his conclusion because of that fact" (2014: 5). I won’t argue that the Taking Condition is incoherent: that nothing can coherently play the role that takings are supposed to play in inference. Instead, I’ll argue that it cannot plausibly explain all the inferential knowledge that…Read more
  •  437
    The Unity of Evidence and Coherence
    In Nick Hughes (ed.), Essays on Epistemic Dilemmas, Oxford University Press. forthcoming.
  •  390
    Belief as a Feeling of Conviction
    In Eric Schwitzgebel & Jonathan Jong (eds.), The Nature of Belief, Oxford University Press. forthcoming.
    This chapter defends the thesis that feeling conviction is sufficient for belief: if you feel conviction that p, then you believe that p. I begin with a neutral characterization of belief in terms of its normative profile: belief is a state that is subject to certain distinctive norms of rationality. The main argument of the chapter is that feelings of conviction are beliefs because they are subject to the same norms of rationality that govern our beliefs. Functionalists often deny that feelings…Read more
  •  32
    Replies to Feldman, Greco, and Malmgren
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 106 (3): 804-821. 2023.
  •  25
    The epistemic role of consciousness
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 106 (3): 778-780. 2023.
  • Why justification matters
    In David K. Henderson & John Greco (eds.), Epistemic Evaluation: Purposeful Epistemology, Oxford University Press Uk. 2015.
  • Epistemic Akrasia
    In The Epistemic Role of Consciousness, Oxford University Press. 2019.
  •  486
    The Problem of Morally Repugnant Beliefs
    In Russ Shafer-Landau (ed.), Oxford Studies in Meta-Ethics, volume 18, Oxford University Press. pp. 218-241. 2023.
    What is the connection between justification and truth in moral epistemology? The primary goal of this paper is to argue that you cannot have justified false beliefs about your own moral obligations. The secondary goal is to explain why not. Some epistemologists embrace a global truth-connection in epistemology, according to which epistemic justification is always factive. In contrast, I endorse a local truth-connection in moral epistemology, which says that epistemic justification is factive wh…Read more
  •  15
    Replies to critics
    Asian Journal of Philosophy 1 (1): 1-15. 2022.
    I reply to my critics in this symposium on my book, The Epistemic Role of Consciousness.
  •  30
    The Epistemic Role of Consciousness By Declan Smithies
    Analysis 81 (4): 772-774. 2022.
  •  20
    Themes from The Epistemic Role of Consciousness
    Asian Journal of Philosophy 1 (1): 1-3. 2022.
    In The Epistemic Role of Consciousness, I argue that phenomenal consciousness plays an indispensable role in explaining our knowledge and justified beliefs about ourselves and the world around us. Without phenomenal consciousness, we cannot know anything at all. The book develops a systematic theory of epistemic justification that applies to knowledge of every kind. In this brief summary, however, I will focus on the epistemology of perception, since that is the main topic addressed by the comme…Read more
  •  762
    According to the Rationality Constraint, our concept of belief imposes limits on how much irrationality is compatible with having beliefs at all. We argue that empirical evidence of human irrationality from the psychology of reasoning and the psychopathology of delusion undermines only the most demanding versions of the Rationality Constraint, which require perfect rationality as a condition for having beliefs. The empirical evidence poses no threat to more relaxed versions of the Rationality Co…Read more
  •  623
    This chapter provides a critical overview of several influential proposals about the epistemic function of higher-order evidence. I start by criticizing accounts of higher-order evidence that appeal to evidential defeat (§1), epistemic conflicts (§2), and unreasonable knowledge (§3). Next, I propose an alternative account that appeals to a combination of improper basing (§4) and non-ideal rationality (§5). Finally, I conclude by summarizing my reasons for preferring this account of higher-order …Read more
  •  1456
    Moral Knowledge By Deduction
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 104 (3): 537-563. 2022.
    How is moral knowledge possible? This paper defends the anti-Humean thesis that we can acquire moral knowledge by deduction from wholly non-moral premises. According to Hume’s Law, as it has become known, we cannot deduce an ‘ought’ from an ‘is’, since it is “altogether inconceivable how this new relation can be a deduction from others, which are entirely different from it” (Hume, 1739, 3.1.1). This paper explores the prospects for a deductive theory of moral knowledge that rejects Hume’s Law.
  •  565
    Moore's Paradox and the Accessibility of Justification
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 85 (2): 273-300. 2011.
    This paper argues that justification is accessible in the sense that one has justification to believe a proposition if and only if one has higher-order justification to believe that one has justification to believe that proposition. I argue that the accessibility of justification is required for explaining what is wrong with believing Moorean conjunctions of the form, ‘p and I do not have justification to believe that p.’
  •  204
    The Epistemic Role of Consciousness
    Oxford University Press. 2019.
    What is the role of consciousness in our mental lives? Declan Smithies argues here that consciousness is essential to explaining how we can acquire knowledge and justified belief about ourselves and the world around us. On this view, unconscious beings cannot form justified beliefs and so they cannot know anything at all. Consciousness is the ultimate basis of all knowledge and epistemic justification.
  •  881
    On the Global Ambitions of Phenomenal Conservatism
    Analytic Philosophy 60 (3): 206-244. 2019.
    What is the role of phenomenal consciousness in grounding epistemic justification? This paper explores the prospects for a global version of phenomenal conservatism inspired by the work of Michael Huemer, according to which all epistemic justification is grounded in phenomenal seemings. I’m interested in this view because of its global ambitions: it seeks to explain all epistemic justification in terms of a single epistemic principle, which says that you have epistemic justification to believe w…Read more
  •  99
  •  1639
    Affective Experience, Desire, and Reasons for Action
    Analytic Philosophy 60 (1): 27-54. 2019.
    What is the role of affective experience in explaining how our desires provide us with reasons for action? When we desire that p, we are thereby disposed to feel attracted to the prospect that p, or to feel averse to the prospect that not-p. In this paper, we argue that affective experiences – including feelings of attraction and aversion – provide us with reasons for action in virtue of their phenomenal character. Moreover, we argue that desires provide us with reasons for action only insofar a…Read more
  •  2749
    The Nature of Cognitive Phenomenology
    Philosophy Compass 8 (8): 744-754. 2013.
    This is the first in a series of two articles that serve as an introduction to recent debates about cognitive phenomenology. Cognitive phenomenology can be defined as the experience that is associated with cognitive activities, such as thinking, reasoning, and understanding. What is at issue in contemporary debates is not the existence of cognitive phenomenology, so defined, but rather its nature and theoretical role. The first article examines questions about the nature of cognitive phenomenolo…Read more
  •  295
    Introspection and Consciousness (edited book)
    Oxford University Press. 2012.
    The topic of introspection stands at the interface between questions in epistemology about the nature of self-knowledge and questions in the philosophy of mind about the nature of consciousness. What is the nature of introspection such that it provides us with a distinctive way of knowing about our own conscious mental states? And what is the nature of consciousness such that we can know about our own conscious mental states by introspection? How should we understand the relationship between con…Read more
  •  927
    Reflection On: On Reflection
    Analysis 76 (1): 55-69. 2016.
    In his book, On Reflection, Hilary Kornblith criticizes what he regards as a chronic tendency in philosophy towards inflating the significance of reflection in ways that manifest a combination of philosophical naiveté and scientific ignorance about how reflection actually works. In these comments, I respond to Kornblith's challenge by sketching an account of the philosophical significance of reflection in the theory of epistemic justification.
  •  409
    Attention: Philosophical and Psychological Essays (edited book)
    Oxford University Press. 2011.
    Attention has been studied in cognitive psychology for more than half a century, but until recently it was largely neglected in philosophy. Now, however, attention has been recognized by philosophers of mind as having an important role to play in our theories of consciousness and of cognition. At the same time, several recent developments in psychology have led psychologists to foundational questions about the nature of attention and its implementation in the brain. As a result there has been a …Read more
  •  2423
    Ideal rationality and logical omniscience
    Synthese 192 (9): 2769-2793. 2015.
    Does rationality require logical omniscience? Our best formal theories of rationality imply that it does, but our ordinary evaluations of rationality seem to suggest otherwise. This paper aims to resolve the tension by arguing that our ordinary evaluations of rationality are not only consistent with the thesis that rationality requires logical omniscience, but also provide a compelling rationale for accepting this thesis in the first place. This paper also defends an account of apriori justifica…Read more