•  648
    The Harm Principle vs. Kantian Criteria for Ensuring Fair, Principled and Just Criminalisation
    Australian Journal of Legal Philosophy 33 (66): 66-99. 2008.
    In this paper, I consider Ripstein and Dan-Cohen's critiques of the 'harm principle'. Ripstein and Dan-Cohen have asserted that the harm principle should be jettisoned, because it allegedly fails to provide a rationale for criminalising certain harmless wrongs that ought to be criminalised. They argue that Kant's second formulation of the categorical imperative and his concept of 'external freedom' are better equipped for ensuring that criminalisation decisions meet the requirements of fairness.…Read more
  •  383
    The Sense and Nonsense of Criminalizing Transfers of Obscene
    Singapore Law Review 26 126-160. 2008.
    The recent distribution of nude photos of a number of high profile Hong Kong celebrities has provoked intense discussion about the state of Hong Kong's obscenity and indecency laws. In this paper, I argue that Hong Kong's laws prohibiting the transfer of obscene and indecent information and images between consenting adults are both under-inclusive and over-inclusive. The Control of Obscene and Indecent Articles Ordinance is under-inclusive in that it does not adequately criminalise grave violati…Read more
  •  52
    Constitutionalizing the Harm Principle
    Criminal Justice Ethics 27 (2): 3-28. 2008.
    In this paper, I argue that a constitutionalized Harm Principle could ensure that people are not jailed unless they deserve it. I do not aim to outline every possible type of bad consequence beyond harm that might be sufficiently serious to justify criminalization. Instead, I focus on criminalization that is backed up with jail terms and I argue that wrongful harm to others provides the only moral and constitutional justification for sending people to jail. Imprisonment harms the prisoner, so sh…Read more
  •  38
    The Moral Limits of Criminalizing Remote Harms
    New Criminal Law Review 10 (3): 370-391. 2007.
    I draw on accessorial liability jurisprudence in an attempt to outline the moral limits of criminalizing people for merely influencing the criminal choices of others. A person's conduct is a remote harm when it is harmless but for the fact that it encourages another independent party to commit a harmful criminal act (a primary harm). For example, the broken windows thesis holds that minor incivilities (such as passive begging) are a precursor to more serious crime. Passive begging allegedly send…Read more
  •  35
    Collective Criminalization and the Constitutional Right to Endanger Others
    Criminal Justice Ethics 28 (2): 168-200. 2009.
    The U.S. Supreme Court recently held that the Second Amendment of the Constitution protects an individual's right to bear and keep arms.1 The Court's opinion will stimulate f...
  •  17
    Recently, William Stuntz, a Harvard law professor, proposed a number of provocative and controversial measures for achieving equality in American criminal justice. In this paper, I argue that Stuntz's radical proposals are not likely to provide a solution to the inequality problem, which as Stuntz acknowledges is predominantly related to the criminalization of drugs. I argue that the imbalance between African American and Anglo-American criminalization would be equalized substantially if drug ta…Read more