•  169
    Freedom as a Philosophical Ideal: Nietzsche and His Antecedents
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 54 (5). 2011.
    Abstract Nietzsche defends an ideal of freedom as the achievement of a ?higher human being?, whose value judgments are a product of a rigorous scrutiny of inherited values and an expression of how the answers to ultimate questions of value are ?settled in him?. I argue that Nietzsche's view is a recognizable descendent of ideas advanced by the ancient Stoics and Spinoza, for whom there is no contradiction between the realization of freedom and the affirmation of fate, and who restrict this freed…Read more
  •  133
    Salvation as a state of mind: The place of acquiescentia in Spinoza's ethics
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 7 (3). 1999.
    (1999). Salvation as a state of mind: The place of acquiescentia in spinoza's ethics. British Journal for the History of Philosophy: Vol. 7, No. 3, pp. 447-473. doi: 10.1080/09608789908571039
  •  111
    Leibniz on compossibility
    Philosophy Compass 4 (6): 962-977. 2009.
    Leibniz's well-known thesis that the actual world is just one among many possible worlds relies on the claim that some possibles are incompossible , meaning that they cannot belong to the same world. Notwithstanding its central role in Leibniz's philosophy, commentators have disagreed about how to understand the compossibility relation. We examine several influential interpretations and demonstrate their shortcomings. We then sketch a new reading, the cosmological interpretation, and argue that …Read more
  •  111
    Spinoza and the dictates of reason
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 51 (5). 2008.
    Spinoza presents the “dictates of reason” as the foundation of “the right way of living”. An influential reading of his position assimilates it to that of Hobbes. The dictates of reason are normative principles that prescribe necessary means to a necessary end: self-preservation. Against this reading I argue that, for Spinoza, the term “dictates of reason” does not refer to a set of prescriptive principles but simply the necessary consequences, or effects, of the mind's determination by adequate…Read more
  •  109
    Nietzsche as perfectionist
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 61 (1): 42-61. 2018.
    Thomas Hurka has argued that Nietzsche’s positive ethical views can be formulated as a version of perfectionism that posits an objective conception of the good as the maximization of power and assigns to all agents the same goal of maximizing the perfection of the best. I show that Hurka’s case for both parts of this interpretation fails on textual grounds and that the kind of theory he proposes is in conflict with Nietzsche’s general approach to morality. The alternative reading for which I arg…Read more
  •  89
    Leibniz and the Rational Order of Nature
    Cambridge University Press. 1995.
    This is the most up-to-date and comprehensive interpretation of the philosophy of Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz. Amongst its other virtues, it makes considerable use of unpublished manuscript sources. The book seeks to demonstrate the systematic unity of Leibniz's thought, in which theodicy, ethics, metaphysics and natural philosophy cohere. The key, underlying idea of the system is the conception of nature as an order designed by God to maximise the opportunities for the exercise of reason. From th…Read more
  •  84
    The Cambridge companion to early modern philosophy (edited book)
    Cambridge University Press. 2006.
    The Cambridge Companion to Early Modern Philosophy is a comprehensive introduction to the central topics and changing shape of philosophical inquiry in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries. It explores one of the most innovative periods in the history of Western philosophy, extending from Montaigne, Bacon and Descartes through Hume and Kant. During this period, philosophers initiated and responded to major intellectual developments in natural science, religion, and politics, transforming in …Read more
  •  79
    Leibniz's Principle of Intelligibility
    History of Philosophy Quarterly 9 (1): 35-49. 1992.
  •  71
    Leibniz: nature and freedom (edited book)
    with Donald Rutherford and J. A. Cover
    Oxford University Press. 2005.
    The revival of Leibniz studies in the past twenty-five years has cast important new light on both the context and content of Leibniz's philosophical thought. Where earlier English-language scholarship understood Leibniz's philosophy as issuing from his preoccupations with logic and language, recent work has recommended an account on which theological, ethical, and metaphysical themes figure centrally in Leibniz's thought throughout his career. The significance of these themes to the development …Read more
  •  65
  •  64
    The Science of the Individual (review)
    The Leibniz Review 16 125-139. 2006.
  •  61
    Leibniz's "analysis of multitude and phenomena into unities and reality"
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 28 (4): 525-552. 1990.
  •  61
    Unity, Reality and Simple Substance
    The Leibniz Review 18 207-224. 2008.
  •  60
  •  53
    Leibniz and the Problem of Soul-Body Union
    The Leibniz Review 2 19-21. 1992.
    A number of recent authors have raised the question of Leibniz’s commitment, during the 1680s and after, to the reality of corporeal substances. In contrast to the standard reading of him as embracing early on a view of substance which is in all essential respects that of the “Monadology”, it has been argued that Leibniz is in fact inclined to recognize two distinct types of substance: on the one hand, unextended soul-like substances ; on the other hand, quasi-Aristotelian corporeal substances. …Read more
  •  51
    Leibniz’s “On Generosity,” With English Translation
    The Leibniz Review 12 15-21. 2002.
    The essay “On Generosity” holds a special place among Leibniz’s ethical writings. In no other text does Leibniz give such prominence to the concept of generosity, or relate it to his central doctrine of justice as the charity of the wise. The circumstances of the piece’s composition are uncertain. Watermark dating of the paper places it in the period 1686-1687. The Academy editors suggest a connection between it and a text by an unknown author, “Discours sur la generosité,” a transcription of wh…Read more
  •  49
    Leibniz and the Rational Order of Nature is intended to offer a broad panorama on Leibniz’s philosophy. Although necessarily selective in its focus, it aspires to a comprehensive understanding of how the different parts of Leibniz’s philosophy — theodicy, ethics, metaphysics, natural philosophy — fit together in a coherent and compelling fashion. In the book, I indicate some of the places where tensions threaten the unity of this scheme. My primary goal, however, is to reconstruct a system that …Read more
  •  45
    Descartes' ethics
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2008.
  •  44
    In Pursuit of Happiness
    Philosophical Topics 31 (1-2): 369-393. 2003.
  •  34
    Hedonism and virtue
    In Peter R. Anstey (ed.), The Oxford handbook of British philosophy in the seventeenth century, Oxford University Press. pp. 415. 2013.
    This chapter examines the views of seventeenth-century British philosophers on the relation between virtue and hedonism, explaining that many philosophers believed that a defense of virtue required rejection of hedonism. It discusses the reformulation of moral philosophy proposed by Thomas Hobbes, and analyzes the reactions of Richard Cumberland and Cambridge Platonists Ralph Cudworth and Henry More. The chapter also considers the revival of Epicureanism and early modern natural law theory.
  •  32
    9. Leibniz and the Stoics: The Consolations of Theodicy
    In Michael J. Latzer & Elmar J. Kremer (eds.), The Problem of Evil in Early Modern Philosophy, University of Toronto Press. pp. 138-164. 2001.
  •  31
    Substance & Individuation in Leibniz (review)
    with Michael Futch
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 39 (4): 591-592. 2001.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Journal of the History of Philosophy 39.4 (2001) 591-592 [Access article in PDF] J. A. Cover and John O'Leary-Hawthorne. Substance & Individuation in Leibniz. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999. Pp. x + 307. Cloth, $59.95. This close engagement with Leibniz's modal metaphysics is as rewarding as it is challenging. Crisply written and tightly argued, the book aims to achieve a balance between what the authors describe as thei…Read more
  •  30
    Leibniz's Metaphysics: A Historical and Comparative Study (review)
    Philosophical Review 101 (4): 853-855. 1992.
  •  28
    Leibniz: An intellectual biography (review)
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 48 (1). 2009.
    This is a superbly crafted and exhaustively researched account of the development of Leibniz’s thought, his ambitious plans and undertakings, his myriad intellectual engagements, and his ceaseless comings and goings across Europe. It captures, accurately and in great detail, the remarkably expansive mind of a singularly creative thinker. It is an extraordinary achievement, for the task of writing an intellectual biography of Leibniz is huge. To read even a portion of what he wrote and read, in t…Read more
  •  27
    Introduction
    American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 76 (4): 523-530. 2002.
  •  25
    Leibniz: Determinist, Theist, Idealist (review)
    Philosophical and Phenomenological Research 61 (1): 226-229. 1994.
  •  24
    Leibniz denies that the actual world possesses the per se unity of a substance. Instead, he seems to hold, the world is limited to the mind-dependent unity of an aggregate. Against this answer, criticized by Kant in his Inaugural Dissertation, I argue that for Leibniz the unity of the actual world is not grounded simply in God’s perception of relations among created substances but in the common dependence of those substances on a unitary cause. First, the actual world is one because every create…Read more
  •  20