•  155
    One reason for the persistent appeal of Don Marquis' ‘future like ours’ argument is that it seems to offer a way to approach the debate about the morality of abortion while sidestepping the difficult task of establishing whether the fetus is a person. This essay argues that in order to satisfactorily address both of the chief objections to FLO – the ‘identity objection’ and the ‘contraception objection’ – Marquis must take a controversial stand on what is most essential to being the kind of enti…Read more
  •  154
    Rape as an essentially contested concept
    Hypatia 16 (2): 43-66. 2001.
    : Because "rape" has such a powerful appraisive meaning, how one defines the term has normative significance. Those who define rape rigidly so as to exclude contemporary feminist understandings are therefore seeking to silence some moral perspectives "by definition." I argue that understanding rape as an essentially contested concept allows the concept sufficient flexibility to permit open moral discourse, while at the same time preserving a core meaning that can frame the discourse
  •  122
    Homosexuality, Misogyny, and God’s Plan
    Faith and Philosophy 16 (2): 213-232. 1999.
    In response to powerful criticisms of older arguments, contemporary defenders of the Church’s traditional stance on homosexuality have fashioned a new kind of argument based upon the special relationship God created between the sexes. In this paper we examine two recent incarnations of this kind of argument and show that both fail to demonstrate the inherent immorality of homosexual relationships, and at most demonstrate that homosexual relationships are inferior to heterosexual relationships in…Read more
  •  119
    Defining Terrorism for Public Policy Purposes: The Group-Target Definition
    Journal of Moral Philosophy 7 (2): 253-278. 2010.
    For the sake of developing and evaluating public policy decisions aimed at combating terrorism, we need a precise public definition of terrorism that distinguishes terrorism from other forms of violence. Ordinary usage does not provide a basis for such a definition, and so it must be stipulative. I propose essentially pragmatic criteria for developing such a stipulative public definition. After noting that definitions previously proposed in the philosophical literature are inadequate based on th…Read more
  •  95
    Richard Swinburne’s formulation of the argument from evil is representative of a pervasive way of understanding the challenge evil poses for theistic belief. But there is an error in Swinburne’s formulation : he fails to consider possible deontological constraints on God’s legitimate responses to evil. To demonstrate the error’s significance, I show that some important objections to Swinburne’s theodicy admit of a novel answer once we correct for Swinburne’s Lapse. While more is needed to show t…Read more
  •  87
    A Guarantee of Universal Salvation?
    Faith and Philosophy 24 (4): 413-432. 2007.
    Recent defenders of the Christian doctrine of eternal damnation have appealed to what I call the “No Guarantee Doctrine” (NG)—the doctrine that not evenGod can ensure both (a) that every person who is saved freely chooses to be saved and (b) that all are saved. Thomas Talbott challenges NG on the groundsthat anyone who is truly free will have no motive to reject God and will infallibly choose salvation. In response to critics of Talbott, I argue that in order toavoid Talbott ’s critique of NG, i…Read more
  •  79
  •  71
    Does the Argument from Evil Assume a Consequentialist Morality?
    Faith and Philosophy 17 (3): 306-319. 2000.
    In this paper, I argue that the some of the most popular and influential formulations of the Argument from Evil (AE) assume a moral perspective that is essentially consequentialist, and would therefore be unacceptable to deontologists. Specifically, I examine formulations of the argument offered by William Rowe and Bruce Russell, both of whom explicitly assert that their formulation of AE is theoretically neutral with respect to consequentialism, and can be read in a way that is unobjectionable …Read more
  •  66
    The Moral Justification of Violence
    Social Theory and Practice 28 (3): 445-464. 2002.
  •  59
    Recently, Eric Yang and Stephen Davis have defended what they call the separationist view of hell against an objection leveled by Jeremy Gwiazda by invoking the concept of hard-heartedness as an account of why some would eternally choose to remain in hell. Gwiazda’s objection to the separationist view of hell is an instance of a broader strategy of objection invoked by other universalists to argue that God could guarantee universal salvation while respecting libertarian freedom—an objection that…Read more
  •  57
    Date Rape and Seduction
    Southwest Philosophy Review 20 (1): 99-106. 2004.
  •  50
    Universalism and autonomy: Towards a comparative defense of universalism
    Faith and Philosophy 18 (2): 222-240. 2001.
    In arecent article, Michael Murray critiques several versions of universalism-that is, the doctrine that in the end all persons are saved. Of particular interest to Murray is Thomas Talbott’s version of universalism (called SU1 by Murray), which puts forward a strategy for ensuring universal salvation that purports to preserve the autonomy of the creatures saved. Murray argues that, on the contrary, the approach put forward in SU1 is not autonomy-preserving at all. I argue that this approach pre…Read more
  •  50
    Punishment and Community: The Reintegrative Theory of Punishment
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 26 (1). 1996.
    There seems to be nearly universal agreement that society cannot do without some form of criminal punishment. At the same time, it is generally acknowledged that punishment, involving as it does the imposition of hardship and suffering, stands in need of justification. What form such a justification should take, however, is a matter of considerable contention, in part because of basic theoretical disagreements on the nature of moral obligation, and in part because of disagreements concerning the…Read more
  •  49
    The Irreconcilability of Pacifism and Just War Theory
    Social Theory and Practice 20 (2): 117-134. 1994.
  •  47
    Rape as an Essentially Contested Concept
    Hypatia 16 (2): 43-66. 2001.
    Because “rape” has such a powerful appraisive meaning, how one defines the term has normative significance. Those who define rape rigidly so as to exclude contemporary feminist understandings are therefore seeking to silence some moral perspectives “by definition.” I argue that understanding rape as an essentially contested concept allows the concept sufficient flexibility to permit open moral discourse, while at the same time preserving a core meaning that can frame the discourse.
  •  46
    Deep ecology and the irrelevance of morality
    Environmental Ethics 18 (4): 411-424. 1996.
    Both Arne Naess and Warwick Fox have argued that deep ecology, in terms of “Selfrealization,” is essentially nonmoral. I argue that the attainment of the ecological Self does not render morality in the richest sense “superfluous,” as Fox suggests. To the contrary, the achievement of the ecological Self is a precondition for being a truly moral person, both from the perspective of a robust Kantian moral frameworkand from the perspective of Aristotelian virtue ethics. The opposition between selfre…Read more
  •  40
    Self-Defense and the Principle of Generic Consistency
    Social Theory and Practice 32 (3): 415-438. 2006.
  •  40
    Sympathy for the Damned
    Southwest Philosophy Review 18 (1): 201-211. 2002.
  •  37
    Response: Personal Pacifism, Another Look
    The Acorn 11 (1): 62-62. 2000.
  •  36
    Efforts to protect endangered species by regulating the use of privately owned lands are routinely resisted by appeal to the private property rights of landowners. Recently, the 'wise-use' movement has emerged as a primary representative of these landowners' claims. In addressing the issues raised by the wise-use movement and others like them, legal scholars and philosophers have typically examined the scope of private property rights and the extent to which these rights should influence public …Read more
  •  35
    Is Annihilation More Severe than Eternal Conscious Torment?
    Southwest Philosophy Review 38 (1): 191-198. 2022.
    In Hell and Divine Goodness, James Spiegel defends the surprising position that of the two dominant non-universalist Christian views on the fate of the damned—the traditionalist view that the damned suffer eternal conscious torment, and the annihilationist view that the damned are put out of existence—the annihilationist view actually posits the more severe fate from the standpoint of a punishment. I argue here that his case for this position rests on two questionable assumptions, and that even …Read more
  •  32
    Review of Liba Taub, Ptolemy's universe; The natural philosophical and ethical foundations of Ptolemy's astronomy. Chicago: Open Court 1993. xiv, 188 p.
  •  31
  •  28
    Terrorism: A Philosophical Investigation, written by Igor Primoratz
    Journal of Moral Philosophy 14 (3): 357-360. 2017.
  •  25
    Nature, Place, and Space
    American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 70 (1): 83-101. 1996.
  •  21
    Substance and Modern Science. By Richard J. Connell (review)
    Modern Schoolman 69 (1): 64-66. 1991.