Temple University
Department of Philosophy
PhD, 1974
Iowa City, Iowa, United States of America
  •  29
    The Epistemology of Spirit Beliefs, written by Hans Van Eyghen
    International Journal for the Study of Skepticism 14 (1): 79-85. 2023.
  •  114
    Review: Hans Radder: The World Observed/The World Conceived (review)
    Mind 117 (466): 505-507. 2008.
  •  8
    Sensible Animism
    In Tiddy Smith (ed.), Animism and Philosophy of Religion, Springer Verlag. pp. 179-197. 2022.
    Animistic religious thought is extremely widespread, and can be found even in religions practiced by “modern” societies. But it is commonly thought to bear the hallmarks of “primitive” thinking processes, which in the anthropological tradition have typically been taken to involve various cognitive errors. Here I am going to argue that this misunderstands and misrepresents the content of such thinking, which is by no means as unsophisticated as it is usually considered to be. I shall be using Rob…Read more
  •  11
    Theodicy in a Vale of Tears
    In Justin P. McBrayer & Daniel Howard‐Snyder (eds.), The Blackwell Companion to the Problem of Evil, Wiley. 2013.
    Theodicies can be distinguished as “hard-nosed” or “good-hearted.” Typical features of each are given. I reject the former; they set the bar too low for God. Considerable discussion is devoted to Eleonore Stump's recent Wandering in Darkness, which sets the standard for good-hearted theodicies. I then develop the notion of a “perfect creature”, a possible being indistinguishable from God except lacking aseity, and argue that God should have created only perfect creatures. Since He did not, He is…Read more
  •  17
    Causation: A Realist Approach
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 50 (3): 605-610. 1990.
  •  10
    Causes and Coincidences (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 55 (2): 465-468. 1995.
  •  130
    Causation and Universals
    Routledge. 1990.
    The world contains objective causal relations and universals, both of which are intimately connected. If these claims are true, they must have far-reaching consequences, breathing new life into the theory of empirical knowledge and reinforcing epistemological realism. Without causes and universals, Professor Fales argues, realism is defeated, and idealism or scepticism wins. Fales begins with a detailed analysis of David Hume's argument that we have no direct experience of necessary connections …Read more
  • Definite Descriptions as Designators
    Mind 85 (n/a): 225. 1976.
  • A Defense of the Given
    Noûs 34 (3): 468-480. 2000.
  •  94
    The attraction between religion and politics is perennial. Sometimes, in its long and checkered history, it has led to an adulterous affair. I want to ask what lies at the heart of this attraction, and whether that can shed any light on the current religious/political scene. But the romance metaphor is at bottom not a good one. I shall argue that, in their originary condition, religion and politics are "closer," both ontologically and in their motivation, than woman and man, closer than siblings…Read more
  • The Structure of Explanations
    Dissertation, Temple University. 1974.
  •  119
    Divine freedom and the choice of a world
    International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 35 (2). 1994.
  • Are Causal Laws Contingent?
    In John Bacon, Keith Campbell & Lloyd Reinhardt (eds.), Ontology, Causality and Mind: Essays in Honour of D.M. Armstrong, Cambridge University Press. 1993.
    It has been nearly a decade and a half since Fred Dretske, David Armstrong and Michael Tooley, having each rejected the Regularity theory, independently proposed that natural laws are grounded in a second-order relation that somehow binds together universals.' (l shall call this the ‘DTA theory’). In this way they sought to overcome the major - and notorious — shortcomings of every version of the Regularity theory: how to provide truth conditions for laws that lack instances; how to distinguish …Read more
  •  130
    A Defense of the Given
    Philosophical Review 108 (1): 128. 1999.
    The “doctrine of the given” that Fales defends holds that there are certain experiences such that we can have justified beliefs about their “contents” that are not based on any other beliefs, and that the rest of our justified empirical beliefs rest on those “basic beliefs.” The features of experience basic beliefs are about are said to be “given.” Fales holds that some basic beliefs are infallible, having a kind of clarity that guarantees their truth to the believer. In addition, some basic bel…Read more
  •  151
    Divine Commands and Moral Obligation
    Philo 13 (2). 2010.
    A popular proof for the existence of God assumes that there are objective moral duties, arguing that this can only be explained by there being a supreme law-giver, namely God. The upshot is either a Divine command theory (DCT) -- or something similar -- or a natural-law theory. I discuss two prominent theories, Robert Adams’s DCT and Stephen Evans’s hybrid DCT/natural-law theory. I argue that they suffer from fatal difficulties. Natural-law theories are plausible, if God exists, but can’t be use…Read more
  •  90
    Turtle epistemology
    Philosophical Studies 169 (2): 339-354. 2014.
    In “Justification Without Awareness”, Michael Bergmann divides internalist epistemologies into those with a strong awareness requirement and those with a weak awareness requirement; he presents a dilemma, hoisting the “strongs” on one horn, and the “weaks” on the other. Here I reply on behalf of the strong-awareness view, presenting what I take to be a more satisfactory, and more fundamental, reply to Bergmann than I believe has been offered by his other critics, and in particular by Rogers and …Read more
  •  64
    Antediluvian Theodicy
    Faith and Philosophy 6 (3): 320-329. 1989.
    This paper is a discussion of Eleonore Stump’s “The Problem of Evil.” Stump, I argue, has attempted a theodicy with several desirable features; among them, an effort to provide a positive account of the compatibility of natural evils with God’s goodness that makes use of specifically Christian doctrines. However, the doctrines Stump makes use of---and, in particular, her conception of hell and her interpretation of original sin---raise, I suggest, more problems than they solve.
  •  7
    Book review (review)
    Foundations of Physics 14 (1): 89-99. 1984.
  • Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (review)
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 13 (4): 524-529. 1983.
  •  120
    Mystical experience as evidence
    International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 40 (1). 1996.
  •  128
    Divine Intervention
    Faith and Philosophy 14 (2): 170-194. 1997.
    Some philosophers deny that science can investigate the supernatural - specifically, the nature and actions of God. If a divine being is atemporal, then, indeed, this seems plausible - but only, I shall argue, because such a being could not causally interact with anything. Here I discuss in detail two major attempts, those of Stump and Kretzmann, and of Leftow, to make sense of theophysical causation on the supposition that God is eternal. These views are carefully worked out, and their failures…Read more
  •  3
    Causal knowledge: What can psychology teach philosophers
    with Edward A. Wasserman
    Journal of Mind and Behavior 13 (1): 1-28. 1992.
    Theories of how organisms learn about cause-effect relations have a history dating back at least to the associationist/mechanistic hypothesis of David Hume. Some contemporary theories of causal learning are descendants of Hume's mechanistic models of conditioning, but others impute principled, rule-based reasoning. Since even primitive animals are conditionable, it is clear that there are built-in mechanical algorithms that respond to cause/effect relations. The evidence suggests that humans ret…Read more
  •  44
    Scientific explanations of mystical experiences: Evan Fales
    Religious Studies 32 (3): 297-313. 1996.
    In Part I of this paper, I took up a challenge posed by Alston , Wainwright , Yandell , and other theists who hold the rather natural view that mystical experiences provide perceptual contact with God, roughly on a par with the access sense experience affords to the natural world. These theists recognize, at the same time, that the plausibility of this view would be significantly compromised by the possibility of scientifically explaining mystical experiences – especially if a scientific explana…Read more