• PhilPapers
  • PhilPeople
  • PhilArchive
  • PhilEvents
  • PhilJobs
  • Sign in
PhilPeople
 
  • Sign in
  • News Feed
  • Find Philosophers
  • Departments
  • Radar
  • Help
 
profile-cover
Drag to reposition
profile picture

Francois Recanati

Institut Jean Nicod
  •  Home
  •  Publications
    192
    • Most Recent
    • Most Downloaded
    • Topics
  •  Events
    27
  •  News and Updates
    205

 More details
  • Institut Jean Nicod
    Department of Philosophy- CNRS
    Regular Faculty
  • All publications (192)
  •  7232
    The Pragmatics of What is Said
    Mind and Language 4 (4): 295-329. 1989.
    Pragmatics, MiscSemantic ContextualismSemantics-Pragmatics Distinction
  •  5616
    On Defining Communicative Intentions
    Mind and Language 1 (3): 213-41. 1986.
    Speaker Meaning and Linguistic MeaningIntention-Based Theories of Meaning
  •  2539
    Deferential concepts: A response to Woodfield
    Mind and Language 15 (4). 2000.
    Concepts, MiscSocial ExternalismQuotationNarrow ContentThe Role of Language in Thought
  •  854
    Referential/attributive: A contextualist proposal
    Philosophical Studies 56 (3). 1989.
    Attributive and Referential Uses of Descriptions
  •  696
    Rigidity and direct reference
    Philosophical Studies 53 (1). 1988.
    Russellian and Direct Reference Theories of MeaningSpecific ExpressionsNouns
  •  686
    Direct reference, meaning, and thought
    Noûs 24 (5): 697-722. 1990.
    Russellian and Direct Reference Theories of Meaning
  •  529
    Quasi-Singular Propositions: The Semantics of Belief Reports
    with Mark Crimmins
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 69 (1). 1995.
    Hidden-Indexical Theories of Attitude AscriptionsPropositions and That-ClausesAttitude Ascriptions, …Read more
    Hidden-Indexical Theories of Attitude AscriptionsPropositions and That-ClausesAttitude Ascriptions, MiscSubstitutivity in Attitude AscriptionsStructured Propositions
  •  430
    What is said
    Synthese 128 (1-2): 75--91. 2001.
    A critique of the purely semantic, minimalist notion of 'what is said'.
    Semantic MinimalismThe Scope of Context-DependenceSpeaker Meaning and Linguistic MeaningThe Nature o…Read more
    Semantic MinimalismThe Scope of Context-DependenceSpeaker Meaning and Linguistic MeaningThe Nature of Contents, MiscSemantics-Pragmatics Distinction
  •  377
    De re and De se
    Dialectica 63 (3): 249-269. 2009.
    For Perry and many authors, de se thoughts are a species of de re thought. In this paper, I argue that de se thoughts come in two varieties: explicit and implicit. While explicit de se thoughts can be construed as a variety of de re thought, implicit de se thoughts cannot: their content is thetic, while the content of de re thoughts is categoric. The notion of an implicit de se thought is claimed to play a central role in accounting for the phenomenon of immunity to error through misidentificati…Read more
    For Perry and many authors, de se thoughts are a species of de re thought. In this paper, I argue that de se thoughts come in two varieties: explicit and implicit. While explicit de se thoughts can be construed as a variety of de re thought, implicit de se thoughts cannot: their content is thetic, while the content of de re thoughts is categoric. The notion of an implicit de se thought is claimed to play a central role in accounting for the phenomenon of immunity to error through misidentification. Lewis has attempted to unify de re and de se in the opposite direction: by reducing de re to de se . This, however, works only if we internalize the acquaintance relations. I criticize Lewis's internalization strategy on the grounds that it rests on Egocentrism (the view that every occurrent thought is ultimately about the thinker at the time of thinking). In the conclusion, I suggest another way of unifying de re and de se , by extending the implicit/explicit distinction to de re thoughts themselves.
    Immunity to Error through MisidentificationFirst-Person ContentsDe Re Belief
  •  369
    Unarticulated constituents
    Linguistics and Philosophy 25 (3): 299-345. 2002.
    In a recent paper (Linguistics and Philosophy 23, 4, June 2000), Jason Stanley argues that there are no `unarticulated constituents', contrary to what advocates of Truth-conditional pragmatics (TCP) have claimed. All truth-conditional effects of context can be traced to logical form, he says. In this paper I maintain that there are unarticulated constituents, and I defend TCP. Stanley's argument exploits the fact that the alleged unarticulated constituents can be `bound', that is, they can be ma…Read more
    In a recent paper (Linguistics and Philosophy 23, 4, June 2000), Jason Stanley argues that there are no `unarticulated constituents', contrary to what advocates of Truth-conditional pragmatics (TCP) have claimed. All truth-conditional effects of context can be traced to logical form, he says. In this paper I maintain that there are unarticulated constituents, and I defend TCP. Stanley's argument exploits the fact that the alleged unarticulated constituents can be `bound', that is, they can be made to vary with the values introduced by operators in the sentence. I show that Stanley's argument rests on a fallacy, and I provide alternative analyses of the data.
    QuantifiersContext and Logical FormContext and Context-Dependence, MiscSemantics-Pragmatics Distinct…Read more
    QuantifiersContext and Logical FormContext and Context-Dependence, MiscSemantics-Pragmatics Distinction
  •  365
    The Fodorian fallacy
    Analysis 62 (4): 285-89. 2002.
    In recent years Fodor has repeatedly argued that nothing epistemic can be essential to, or constitutive of, any concept. This holds in virtue of a constraint which Fodor dubs the Compositionality Constraint. I show that Fodor's argument is fallacious because it rests on an ambiguity.
    Atomist Theories of ConceptsCompositionalityConcept PossessionThe Language of Thought
  •  363
    Direct Reference: From Language to Thought
    Blackwell. 1993.
    This volume puts forward a distinct new theory of direct reference, blending insights from both the Fregean and the Russellian traditions, and fitting the general theory of language understanding used by those working on the pragmatics of natural language.
    Russellian and Direct Reference Theories of Meaning
  •  321
    How narrow is narrow content?
    Dialectica 48 (3-4): 209-29. 1994.
    SummaryIn this paper I discuss two influential views in the philosophy of mind: the two‐component picture draws a distinction between ‘narrow content’ and ‘broad content’, while radical externalism denies that there is such a thing as narrow content. I argue that ‘narrow content’ is ambiguous, and that the two views can be reconciled. Instead of considering that there is only one question and three possible answers corresponding to Cartesian internalism, the two‐component picture, and radical ex…Read more
    SummaryIn this paper I discuss two influential views in the philosophy of mind: the two‐component picture draws a distinction between ‘narrow content’ and ‘broad content’, while radical externalism denies that there is such a thing as narrow content. I argue that ‘narrow content’ is ambiguous, and that the two views can be reconciled. Instead of considering that there is only one question and three possible answers corresponding to Cartesian internalism, the two‐component picture, and radical externalism respectively, I show that there are two distinct questions: ‘Are mental contents internal to the individual?’ and, ‘Are mental contents analysable in two‐components?’ Both questions can be given a positive or a negative answer, in such a way that there are four, rather than three, possible views to be distinguished. The extra view whose possibility emerges in this framework is that which mixes radical externalism with the two‐component picture. It agrees with radical externalism that there cannot be ‘solipsistic’ contents: content is not an intrinsic property of the states of an individual organism, but a relational property. It also agrees with the two‐component picture, on a certain interpretation: the broad content of a psychological state depends upon what actually causes that state, but the narrow content depends only on what normally causes this type of state to occur. In the last section of the paper, I deal with internal representation which seem to be independent even of the normal environment. I show that such contents are themselves independent of the normal environment only in a relative sense: they are locally independent of the normal environment, yet still depend on it via the concepts to which they are connected in the concept system.
    Narrow ContentTwin Earth and ExternalismVarieties of Content Externalism, MiscTwo-Dimensionalism abo…Read more
    Narrow ContentTwin Earth and ExternalismVarieties of Content Externalism, MiscTwo-Dimensionalism about ContentContent Internalism and Externalism, Miscellaneous
  •  275
    Perceptual concepts: in defence of the indexical model
    Synthese 190 (10): 1841-1855. 2013.
    Francois Recanati presents the basic features of the *indexical model* of mental files, and defends it against several interrelated objections. According to this model, mental files refer to objects in a way that is analogous to that of indexicals in language: a file refers to an object in virtue of a contextual relation between them. For instance, perception and attention provide the basis for demonstrative files. Several objections, some of them from David Papineau, concern the possibility of …Read more
    Francois Recanati presents the basic features of the *indexical model* of mental files, and defends it against several interrelated objections. According to this model, mental files refer to objects in a way that is analogous to that of indexicals in language: a file refers to an object in virtue of a contextual relation between them. For instance, perception and attention provide the basis for demonstrative files. Several objections, some of them from David Papineau, concern the possibility of files to preserve and add information about objects across contexts. How is it possible to think about the same object when the subject no longer is in the original context? How is it possible to think of a perceived object as already known? Can this be done without an explicit identity judgment? Recanati answers these questions by invoking mental files of non-basic kinds and by describing the cognitive dynamics in which they take part.
    The Nature of ContentsPerception-Based Theories of ConceptsIndexicals, Misc
  •  271
    Contextual Dependence and Definite Descriptions
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 87 57-73. 1987.
    François Recanati; IV*—Contextual Dependence and Definite Descriptions, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 87, Issue 1, 1 June 1987, Pages 57–74, h.
    Descriptions
  •  264
    Does linguistic communication rest on inference?
    Mind and Language 17 (1-2). 2002.
    It is often claimed that, because of semantic underdetermination, one can determine the content of an utterance only by appealing to pragmatic considerations concerning what the speaker means, what his intentions are. This supports ‘inferentialism' : the view that, in contrast to perceptual content, communicational content is accessed indirectly, via an inference. As against this view, I argue that primary pragmatic processes (the pragmatic processes that are involved in the determination of tru…Read more
    It is often claimed that, because of semantic underdetermination, one can determine the content of an utterance only by appealing to pragmatic considerations concerning what the speaker means, what his intentions are. This supports ‘inferentialism' : the view that, in contrast to perceptual content, communicational content is accessed indirectly, via an inference. As against this view, I argue that primary pragmatic processes (the pragmatic processes that are involved in the determination of truth-conditional content) need not involve an inference from premisses concerning what the speaker can possibly intend by his utterance. Indeed, they need not involve any inference at all : communication, I argue, is as direct as perception.
    Linguistic CommunicationContext and Context-Dependence, MiscInferenceSemantics-Pragmatics Distinctio…Read more
    Linguistic CommunicationContext and Context-Dependence, MiscInferenceSemantics-Pragmatics DistinctionEpistemology of TestimonyConsciousness and Content, Misc
  •  248
    Content, Mood, and Force
    Philosophy Compass 8 (7): 622-632. 2013.
    In this survey paper, I start from two classical theses of speech act theory: that speech act content is uniformly propositional and that sentence mood encodes illocutionary force. These theses have been questioned in recent work, both in philosophy and linguistics. The force/content distinction itself – a cornerstone of 20‐century philosophy of language – has come to be rejected by some theorists, unmoved by the famous ‘Frege–Geach’ argument. The paper reviews some of these debates.
    Linguistic ForceQuestionsSpeech ActsThe Unity of the Proposition
  •  217
    Mental Files: Replies to my Critics
    Disputatio 5 (36): 207-242. 2013.
    My responses to seven critical reviews of my book *Mental Files* published in a special issue of the journal Disputatio, edited by F. Salis. The reviewers are: Keith Hall, David Papineau, Annalisa Coliva and Delia Belleri, Peter Pagin, Thea Goodsell, Krista Lawlor and Manuel Garcia-Carpintero.
    The Nature of ContentsNames, MiscFirst-Person ContentsLinguistic Communication
  •  215
    It is raining (somewhere)
    Linguistics and Philosophy 30 (1): 123-146. 2005.
    The received view about meteorological predicates like ‘rain’ is that they carry an argument slot for a location which can be filled explicitly or implicitly. The view assumes that ‘rain’, in the absence of an explicit location, demands that the context provide a specific location. In an earlier article in this journal, I provided a counter-example, viz. a context in which ‘it is raining’ receives a location-indefinite interpretation. On the basis of that example, I argued that when there is tac…Read more
    The received view about meteorological predicates like ‘rain’ is that they carry an argument slot for a location which can be filled explicitly or implicitly. The view assumes that ‘rain’, in the absence of an explicit location, demands that the context provide a specific location. In an earlier article in this journal, I provided a counter-example, viz. a context in which ‘it is raining’ receives a location-indefinite interpretation. On the basis of that example, I argued that when there is tacit references to a location, it takes place for pragmatic reasons and casts no light on the semantics of meteorological predicates. Since then, several authors have reanalysed the counter-example, so as to make it compatible with the standard view. I discuss those attempts and argue that my account is superior.
    Context and Context-DependencePredicates and Context-DependenceSemantics-Pragmatics DistinctionVaria…Read more
    Context and Context-DependencePredicates and Context-DependenceSemantics-Pragmatics DistinctionVariablesVerbs, Misc
  •  212
    Mental Files
    Oxford University Press. 2012.
    Over the past fifty years the philosophy of language and mind has been dominated by a nondescriptivist approach to content and reference. This book attempts to recast and systematize that approach by offering an indexical model in terms of mental files. According to Recanati, we refer through mental files, the function of which is to store information derived through certain types of contextual relation the subject bears to objects in his or her environment. The reference of a file is determined…Read more
    Over the past fifty years the philosophy of language and mind has been dominated by a nondescriptivist approach to content and reference. This book attempts to recast and systematize that approach by offering an indexical model in terms of mental files. According to Recanati, we refer through mental files, the function of which is to store information derived through certain types of contextual relation the subject bears to objects in his or her environment. The reference of a file is determined relationally, not satisfactionally, so a file is not to be equated to the body of (mis-)information it contains. Mental files are the mental equivalent of singular terms, and the reference of linguistic expressions is inherited from that of the files we associate with them. On this approach, mental files, the vehicles of singular thought, do all the work of so-called 'modes of presentation' in Fregean and neo-Russellian theories.
    IntentionalityDescriptive Theories of ReferenceRussellian and Direct Reference Theories, MiscFregean…Read more
    IntentionalityDescriptive Theories of ReferenceRussellian and Direct Reference Theories, MiscFregean Sense
  •  209
    Relational belief reports
    Philosophical Studies 100 (3): 255-272. 2000.
    De Re BeliefSubstitutivity in Attitude AscriptionsHidden-Indexical Theories of Attitude AscriptionsP…Read more
    De Re BeliefSubstitutivity in Attitude AscriptionsHidden-Indexical Theories of Attitude AscriptionsPropositional Attitudes, Misc
  •  199
    ‘That’-clauses as existential quantifiers
    Analysis 64 (3): 229-235. 2004.
    Following Panaccio, 'John believes that p' is analysed as 'For some x such that x is true if and only if p, John believes x'. On this view the complement clause 'that p' acts as a restricted existential quantifier and it contributes a higher-order property.
    Generalized QuantifiersContext and Logical FormAttitude Ascriptions, MiscPropositions and That-Claus…Read more
    Generalized QuantifiersContext and Logical FormAttitude Ascriptions, MiscPropositions and That-Clauses
  •  199
    Crazy minimalism
    Mind and Language 21 (1). 2006.
    Review of Insensitive Semantics, by H. Cappelen and E. Lepore.
    Semantic MinimalismThe Scope of Context-DependenceSemantics-Pragmatics DistinctionContext and Contex…Read more
    Semantic MinimalismThe Scope of Context-DependenceSemantics-Pragmatics DistinctionContext and Context-Dependence, Misc
  •  190
    Literal Meaning
    Cambridge University Press. 2002.
    According to the dominant position among philosophers of language today, we can legitimately ascribe determinate contents to natural language sentences, independently of what the speaker actually means. This view contrasts with that held by ordinary language philosophers fifty years ago: according to them, speech acts, not sentences, are the primary bearers of content. François Recanati argues for the relevance of this controversy to the current debate about semantics and pragmatics. Is 'what is…Read more
    According to the dominant position among philosophers of language today, we can legitimately ascribe determinate contents to natural language sentences, independently of what the speaker actually means. This view contrasts with that held by ordinary language philosophers fifty years ago: according to them, speech acts, not sentences, are the primary bearers of content. François Recanati argues for the relevance of this controversy to the current debate about semantics and pragmatics. Is 'what is said' determined by linguistic conventions, or is it an aspect of 'speaker's meaning'? Do we need pragmatics to fix truth-conditions? What is 'literal meaning'? To what extent is semantic composition a creative process? How pervasive is context-sensitivity? Recanati provides an original and insightful defence of 'contextualism', and offers an informed survey of the spectrum of positions held by linguists and philosophers working at the semantics/pragmatics interface.
    Context and Logical FormContext and Context-Dependence, MiscSemantics-Pragmatics DistinctionPragmati…Read more
    Context and Logical FormContext and Context-Dependence, MiscSemantics-Pragmatics DistinctionPragmatics, MiscNonliteral MeaningReferencePredicates and Context-Dependence
  •  180
    Literal/nonliteral
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 25 (1). 2001.
    Nonliteral MeaningMetaphorImplicature, MiscSemantics-Pragmatics DistinctionConversational Implicatur…Read more
    Nonliteral MeaningMetaphorImplicature, MiscSemantics-Pragmatics DistinctionConversational Implicature
  •  176
    Truth-Conditional Pragmatics
    Oxford University Press. 2010.
    This book argues against the traditional understanding of the semantics/pragmatics divide and puts forward a radical alternative. Through half a dozen case studies, it shows that what an utterance says cannot be neatly separated from what the speaker means. In particular, the speaker's meaning endows words with senses that are tailored to the situation of utterance and depart from the conventional meanings carried by the words in isolation. This phenomenon of ‘pragmatic modulation’ must be taken…Read more
    This book argues against the traditional understanding of the semantics/pragmatics divide and puts forward a radical alternative. Through half a dozen case studies, it shows that what an utterance says cannot be neatly separated from what the speaker means. In particular, the speaker's meaning endows words with senses that are tailored to the situation of utterance and depart from the conventional meanings carried by the words in isolation. This phenomenon of ‘pragmatic modulation’ must be taken into account in theorizing about semantic content, for it interacts with the grammar-driven process of semantic composition. Because of that interaction, the book argues, the content of a sentence always depends upon the context in which it is used. This claim defines Contextualism, a view which has attracted considerable attention in recent years, and of which the author of this book is one of the main proponents.
    Linguistic CommunicationSemantics-Pragmatics DistinctionAdjectives, MiscIndexicals, MiscQuotation
  •  172
    Domains of discourse
    Linguistics and Philosophy 19 (5). 1996.
    In the first part of this paper I present a defence of the Austinian semantic approach to incomplete quantifiers and similar phenomena (section 2-4). It is part of my defence of Austinian semantics that it incorporates a cognitive dimension (section 4). This cognitive dimension makes it possible to connect Austinian semantics to various cognitive theories of discourse interpretation. In the second part of the paper (sections 5-7), I establish connections between Austinian semantics and four part…Read more
    In the first part of this paper I present a defence of the Austinian semantic approach to incomplete quantifiers and similar phenomena (section 2-4). It is part of my defence of Austinian semantics that it incorporates a cognitive dimension (section 4). This cognitive dimension makes it possible to connect Austinian semantics to various cognitive theories of discourse interpretation. In the second part of the paper (sections 5-7), I establish connections between Austinian semantics and four particular theories: • the theory of reference and modes of presentation in terms of information files (see e.g. Perry 1993), • the theory of discourse interpretation as involving a process of context selection (see Sperber and Wilson 1986), • the theory of informational structure (for a survey, see Lambrecht 1994), • the theory of mental spaces (Fauconnier 1985)
    Context and Context-Dependence, MiscQuantifier RestrictionSituation SemanticsDiscourseReference, Mis…Read more
    Context and Context-Dependence, MiscQuantifier RestrictionSituation SemanticsDiscourseReference, Misc
  •  162
    Fictional, Metafictional, Parafictional
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 118 (1): 25-54. 2018.
    Fictional CharactersEmpty Names
  •  162
    Can we believe what we do not understand?
    Mind and Language 12 (1): 84-100. 1997.
    In a series of papers, Sperber provides the following analysis of the phenomenon of ill-understood belief (or 'quasi-belief', as I call it): (i) the quasi-believer has a validating meta-belief, to the effect that a certain representation is true; yet (ii) that representation does not give rise to a plain belief, because it is 'semi-propositional'. In this paper I discuss several aspects of this treatment. In particular, I deny that the representation accepted by the quasi-believer is semanticall…Read more
    In a series of papers, Sperber provides the following analysis of the phenomenon of ill-understood belief (or 'quasi-belief', as I call it): (i) the quasi-believer has a validating meta-belief, to the effect that a certain representation is true; yet (ii) that representation does not give rise to a plain belief, because it is 'semi-propositional'. In this paper I discuss several aspects of this treatment. In particular, I deny that the representation accepted by the quasi-believer is semantically indeterminate, and I reject Sperber's claim that quasi-belief is a credal attitude distinct from plain belief.
    The Role of Language in ThoughtBelief, MiscSocial ExternalismQuotationConcepts, Misc
  •  159
    Open quotation
    Mind 110 (439): 637-687. 2001.
    The issues addressed in philosophical papers on quotation generally concern only a particular type of quotation, which I call ‘closed quotation’. The other main type, ‘open quotation’, is ignored, and this neglect leads to bad theorizing. Not only is a general theory of quotation out of reach: the specific phenomenon of closed quotation itself cannot be properly understood if it is not appropriately situated within the kind to which it belongs. Once the distinction between open and closed quotat…Read more
    The issues addressed in philosophical papers on quotation generally concern only a particular type of quotation, which I call ‘closed quotation’. The other main type, ‘open quotation’, is ignored, and this neglect leads to bad theorizing. Not only is a general theory of quotation out of reach: the specific phenomenon of closed quotation itself cannot be properly understood if it is not appropriately situated within the kind to which it belongs. Once the distinction between open and closed quotation has been drawn and properly appreciated, it is tempting to consider that only closed quotation is relevant to semantics. Open quotation is more a matter of pragmatics: it is a matter of what people do with words, rather than a matter of content and truth-conditions. In this way one can provide the beginning of a justification for the neglect of open quotation in current semantic theorizing. There is some truth in this view, yet the phenomenon of ‘mixed quotation’, investigated at length in this paper, is interesting precisely because it shows that things are not so simple. Important issues concerning the interface between semantics and pragmatics will thus be raised.
    QuotationReference, Misc
  • Prev.
  • 1
  • 2
  • 3
  • 4
  • 5
  • 6
  • 7
  • Next
PhilPeople logo

On this site

  • Find a philosopher
  • Find a department
  • The Radar
  • Index of professional philosophers
  • Index of departments
  • Help
  • Acknowledgments
  • Careers
  • Contact us
  • Terms and conditions

Brought to you by

  • The PhilPapers Foundation
  • The American Philosophical Association
  • Centre for Digital Philosophy, Western University
PhilPeople is currently in Beta Sponsored by the PhilPapers Foundation and the American Philosophical Association
Feedback