•  9
    George Berkeley: a philosophical life (review)
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 31 (3): 557-561. 2023.
    The book under review here is a thorough and enlightening look at how Berkeley's life and philosophy intertwined. The fact that this review focuses on some points where I disagree with the author s...
  • The Right to Walk Away
    In Aviezer Tucker & Gian Piero De Bellis (eds.), Panarchy: Political Theories of Non-Territorial States, Routledge. 2015.
  •  7
    C.S. Lewis was a major public intellectual in Britain, beginning from the late 1930s and continuing to his death in 1963. In both his non-fiction, especially The Abolition of Man, and his fiction, most importantly in That Hideous Strength, he offers a critique of rationalism and scientism that is often strikingly similar to those that Michael Oakeshott penned in the late 1940s and early 1950s. This essay examines the question to what extent this similarity is merely superficial, and to what exte…Read more
  •  13
    Critics of Enlightenment Rationalism (edited book)
    with Kenneth B. McIntyre
    Palgrave-Macmillan. 2020.
    This book provides an overview of some of the most important critics of “Enlightenment rationalism.” The subjects of the volume—including, among others, Burke, Kierkegaard, Nietzsche, T.S. Eliot, Wittgenstein, Heidegger, C.S. Lewis, Gabriel Marcel, Russell Kirk, and Jane Jacobs—do not share a philosophical tradition as much as a skeptical disposition toward the notion, common among modern thinkers, that there is only one standard of rationality or reasonableness, and that that one standard is or…Read more
  •  17
    Philosophy of nature (review)
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 26 (2): 396-399. 2018.
  •  5
    Oakeshott on Rome and America
    Imprint Academic. 2012.
    The political systems of the Roman Republic were based almost entirely on tradition, “the way of the ancestors”, rather than on a written constitution. While the founders of the American Republic looked to ancient Rome as a primary model for their enterprise, nevertheless, in line with the rationalist spirit of their age, the American founders attempted to create a rational set of rules that would guide the conduct of American politics, namely, the US Constitution.These two examples offer a stri…Read more
  •  230
    Ideal Types and the Historical Method
    Collingwood and British Idealism Studies 13 (1): 53-68. 2007.
    A number of social theorists have contended that the essence of historical analysis is the employment of ideal types to comprehend past goings-on. But, while acknowledging that the study of history through ideal types can yield genuine insight, we may still ask if it represents the full emancipation of historical understanding from other modes of conceiving the past. This paper follows Michael Oakeshott's work on the philosophy of history in arguing that explaining the historical past by means o…Read more
  •  962
    Was Berkeley a Subjective Idealist?
    Collingwood and British Idealism Studies 21 (2): 157-184. 2015.
    Subjective idealism can be defined as the view that ‘the objective world independent of man does not exist; it is the product of man's subjective cognitive abilities, sensations, and perceptions’. George Berkeley often is said to be the founder of this species of idealism, and when someone wants to offer an example of a subjective idealist, Berkeley is usually the first person who comes to mind. However, those making this claim largely seem to be only passingly familiar with Berkeley’s work, som…Read more
  •  45
    The necessity of the a priori in science
    Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 18 (4): 417-429. 2006.
    Jeffrey Friedman has attempted to make a case for limiting state social engineering that is based on the skeptical epistemology of Sir Karl Popper. But Popper's epistemology is flawed, both in its rejection of a priori theorizing and its insistence on empirical falsification rather than confirmation. Classical liberalism of the sort that Friedman advocates requires, as its basis, positive knowledge of economics and social reality—not Popperian skepticism.
  •  23
    History is Not Historicism
    Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 21 (4): 467-474. 2009.
    ABSTRACT Nassim Taleb’s dismissal of history as based on the “narrative fallacy”—which reads our present knowledge of past events into our reconstruction of the past—is based on a fundamental misconception of what historians actually do. Historians do not, as Taleb presumes, try to infer general, predictive laws from “hard” facts, as do natural scientists; instead their aim is to discover the causes of unique historical facts among antecedent facts. This is no different, in principle, from “narr…Read more
  •  68
    Liberty versus libertarianism
    Politics, Philosophy and Economics 12 (1): 48-67. 2013.
    This paper aims to persuade its reader that libertarianism, at least in several of its varieties, is a species of the genus Michael Oakeshott referred to as ‘rationalism in politics’. I hope to demonstrate, employing the work of Oakeshott, as well as Aristotle and Onora O’Neill, how many libertarian theorists, who generally have a sincere and admirable commitment to personal liberty, have been led astray by the rationalist promise that we might be able to approach deductive certainty concerning …Read more
  •  46
    Is there a right to immigration?: A libertarian perspective (review)
    with Walter Block
    Human Rights Review 5 (1): 46-71. 2003.
  •  248
    Winch on Following a Rule: A Wittgensteinian Critique of Oakeshott
    Collingwood and British Idealism Studies 18 (2): 167-175. 2012.
    Peter Winch famously critiqued Michael Oakeshott's view of human conduct. He argued that Oakeshott had missed the fact that truly human conduct is conduct that 'follows a rule.' This paper argues that, as is sometimes the case with Oakeshott, what seems, on the surface, to be a disagreement with another, somewhat compatible thinker about a matter of detail in some social theory in fact turns out to point to a deeper philosophical divide. In particular, I contend, Winch, as typical of those who o…Read more
  •  16
    History is Not Historicism
    Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 21 (4): 467-474. 2009.
    ABSTRACT Nassim Taleb’s dismissal of history as based on the “narrative fallacy”—which reads our present knowledge of past events into our reconstruction of the past—is based on a fundamental misconception of what historians actually do. Historians do not, as Taleb presumes, try to infer general, predictive laws from “hard” facts, as do natural scientists; instead their aim is to discover the causes of unique historical facts among antecedent facts. This is no different, in principle, from “narr…Read more
  •  14
    Philosophy between the lines: the lost history of esoteric writing (review)
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 24 (6): 1214-1217. 2014.
  •  56
    Economics and Its Modes
    Collingwood and British Idealism Studies 14 (2): 128-157. 2008.
    Often different schools or styles of doing economics are seen as inevitably at odds with each other, so that one must be crowned 'correct' and the others vanquished as defective. However, if they actually represent alternative but potentially enlightening views of economic phenomena, then it will be foolish exclusively to pursue one approach at the expense of all others. This paper argues that the latter is a more accurate view of economics than is the former
  •  32
  •  178
    The Idea of a Social Cycle
    with Andreas Hoffman
    The paper aims to explore what it means for something to be a social cycle, for a theory to be a social cycle theory, and to offer a suggestion for a simple, yet, we believe, fundamentally grounded schema for categorizing them. We show that a broad range of cycle theories can be described within the concept of disruption and adjustments. Further, many important cycle theories are true endogenous social cycle theories in which the theory provides a reason why the cycle should recur. We find that …Read more
  •  105
    Hans-Herman Hoppe's argumentation ethic: A critique
    Journal of Libertarian Studies 20 (2): 53-64. 2006.
    ONE OF THE MOST prominent theorists of anarcho-capitalism is Hans- Hermann Hoppe. In what is perhaps his most famous result, the argumentation ethic for libertarianism, he purports to establish an a priori defense of the justice of a social order based exclusively on pri- vate property. Hoppe claims that all participants in a debate must presuppose the libertarian principle that every person owns himself, since the principle underlies the very concept of argumentation. Some libertarians (e.g., R…Read more