•  200
    Berkeley's idealism: a critical examination
    Oxford University Press. 2011.
    Berkeley's Idealism both advances Berkeley scholarship and serves as a useful guide for teachers and students.
  •  192
    Descartes and the Meditations
    Philosophical Review 114 (1): 122-125. 2005.
  •  107
    Kant's refutation of idealism: A reply to Chignell
    Philosophical Quarterly 61 (242): 175-183. 2011.
    I reply to the most important criticisms made by Chignell of my ‘Kant's Refutation of Idealism’. I also introduce a new consideration which brings out more fully the power of Kant's argument
  •  95
    I argue that philonous gives two versions of the argument from perceptual relativity--One for the secondary qualities and another for the primary. Further, Both versions ultimately turn on the epistemological assumption that every case of perceiving, Regardless of the conditions of observation, Is a case of "knowing" the character of some "object". This assumption is made in order to avoid a vicious regress that arises when one tries to understand how perceptual knowledge is possible
  •  91
    Anti-Berkeley
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 16 (2). 2008.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  90
    A solid grasp of the main themes and arguments of the seventeenth century philosopher Rene Descartes is an essential tool towards understanding modern thought, and a necessary entree to the work of the empiricists and Immanuel Kant, and to the study of contemporary epistemology and philosophy of mind. Clear and accessible, this book serves as an introduction to Descartes's ideas for undergraduates and as a sophisticated companion to his Meditations for more advanced readers. After a thorough dis…Read more
  •  88
    A Refutation of Rowe’s Critique of Anselm’s Ontological Argument
    Faith and Philosophy 5 (2): 193-202. 1988.
    In William L. Rowe’s “The Ontological Argument,” an essay that appears in the most recent editions of Feinberg’s Reason and Responsibility and as a chapter in Rowe’s Philosophy of Religion, Rowe reconstructs Anselm’s Proslogium II argument for the existence of God, surveys critically several standard objections to it, and presents an original critique. Although Rowe’s reconstruction is perspicuous and his criticisms of the standard objections are judicious, his own critique, I argue, leaves Anse…Read more
  •  84
    Kant's Refutation of Idealism: Once More Unto the Breach
    Kantian Review 17 (2): 191-195. 2012.
    In ‘Kant's Refutation of Idealism’ (Noûs, 47), I defend a version of the Refutation, pioneered by Paul Guyer inKant and the Claims of Knowledge, whose core idea is that the only way that one can know the order of one's own past experiences, except in certain rare cases, is by correlating them with the successive states of perceived external objects that caused the experiences. Andrew Chignell has offered a probing critique of my reconstruction of Kant's argument (Philosophical Quarterly, 60), an…Read more
  •  78
    Berkeley on immediate perception: Once more unto the breach
    Philosophical Quarterly 56 (225). 2006.
    I have previously argued that within an argument to show that we cannot perceive the causes of our sensations, Berkeley's Philonous conflates a psychological and an epistemic sense of 'immediately perceive', and uses the principle of perceptual immediacy (PPI), that whatever is perceived by the senses is immediately perceived. George Pappas has objected that Berkeley does not operate with either of these concepts of immediate perception, and does not subscribe to (PPI). But I show that Berkeley'…Read more
  •  75
    Anyone familiar with some of Dewey’s major works knows that they are highly critical of nearly all that has traditionally passed under the name of “epistemology” or “theory of knowledge”. Even a casual reading of a few chapters of Reconstruction in Philosophy, The Quest for Certainty or Experience and Nature reveals Dewey’s iconoclasm toward “that species of confirmed intellectual lock-jaw called epistemology”. The source of this attitude is Dewey’s belief that all theories of knowledge previous…Read more
  •  68
    Three Questions about Treatise 1.4.2
    Hume Studies 33 (1): 115-153. 2007.
    Why does Hume think that the "distinct existence" of sensible objects implies their "continu'd existence"? Does Hume have any reason for thinking that objects have an intermittent existence, other than that they lack a "distinct" existence? Why does Hume think that the inference from the "coherence" of our impressions to the continued existence of objects is "at bottom" considerably different from causal reasoning? The answers proposed are, respectively, that perceptually delimited objects would…Read more
  •  63
    Perceptual Knowledge
    Reidel. 1980.
    INTRODUCTION This book is a systematic study of the problem of perception and knowledge. I intend to analyze the problem, to expound and criticize the most ...
  •  61
    Regularity, Conditionality, and Asymmetry in Causation
    The Proceedings of the Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 7 129-138. 2000.
    In this paper I explore the relationship between the “Humean” regularity view of causation, the view that a cause is a necessary condition of its effect, and the asymmetry of causation—the principle that if an event e1 causes e2, then it is false that e2 causes e1. I argue that the regularity view, in combination with the view that a cause is a necessary condition of its effect, is inconsistent with the asymmetry of causation, and that the inconsistency can be removed by a modification of the vi…Read more
  •  57
    David Hume's _Treatise on Human Nature_ and _Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding_ are amongst the most widely-studies texts on philosophy. _Hume's Epistemology and Metaphysics: An Introduction_ presents in a clear, concise and accessible manner the key themes of these texts. Georges Dicker clarifies Hume's views on meaning, knowledge, causality, and sense perception step by step and provides us with a sharp picture of how philosophical thinking has been influenced by Hume. Accessible to anyon…Read more
  •  53
    Kant's masterpiece, Critique of Pure Reason, is universally recognized to be among the most difficult of all philosophical writing, and yet it is required reading in almost every course that covers modern philosophy. Most students find Critique of Pure Reason impenetrable without the help of secondary sources. While there are numerous advanced scholarly works on the topic, Dicker's is the first treatment explicitly designed for undergraduates to read alongside the primary text, rendering Kant's …Read more
  •  50
    Review: Forster, Kant and Skepticism
    European Journal of Philosophy 18 (4): 609-615. 2010.
  •  49
    Hume's Fork Revisited
    History of Philosophy Quarterly 8 (4). 1991.
  •  46
    Hume Studies Referees, 2006–2007
    with Margaret Atherton, Tom Beauchamp, Deborah Boyle, Emily Carson, Dorothy Coleman, Angela Coventry, Shelagh Crooks, Remy Debes, and Paul Draper
    Hume Studies 33 (2): 385-387. 2007.
  •  41
    The Moderns in an Introductory Analytic Course
    Teaching Philosophy 13 (3): 265-272. 1990.
  •  40
    Book reviews (review)
    with Tom Regan
    Journal of Value Inquiry 5 (4): 315-318. 1971.
  •  39
    “Cogito, Ergo Sum”: Proof or Petitio?
    The European Legacy 27 (3-4): 269-282. 2022.
    ABSTRACT E. M. Curley has said that Descartes’ cogito, ergo sum “is as obscure on examination as it is compelling at first glance.” Why should that be? Maybe because the cogito raises so many textual and interpretive questions. Is it an argument or an intuition? If it is an argument, does it require an additional premise? Is it best interpreted as a “performance?” Is it best seen as the discovery that any reason proposed for doubting its success entails the meditator’s existence? And so on. But …Read more
  •  36
    The problem of perception, by A. D. Smith
    European Journal of Philosophy 14 (3). 2006.
  •  33
    Is there a problem about perception and knowledge?
    American Philosophical Quarterly 15 (3): 165-176. 1978.
  •  31
    Warranted Assertibility and the Uniformity of Nature
    Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 9 (2). 1973.
    Dewey defines knowledge as the outcome of competent inquiry. but knowledge is for dewey fundamentally predictive. this gives rise to a difficulty: should the course of nature change, a man might both know something (having carried out the relevant inquiry) and not know it (his relevant predictions being false). this difficulty is set out formally, and a solution is proposed in terms of dewey's concept of warranted assertibility
  •  30
    Cognition and Commitment in Hume’s Philosophy (review)
    Review of Metaphysics 52 (2): 447-449. 1998.
    Garrett seeks mainly to show that Hume’s position is internally consistent and to build a portrait of Hume as essentially a cognitive psychologist.