•  1
    Conceptual Role Semantics
    In Ernie Lepore & Barry C. Smith (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Language, Oxford University Press. pp. 295. 2005.
  •  397
    Practical reasoning
    In Alfred R. Mele (ed.), The philosophy of action, Oxford University Press. pp. 431--63. 1997.
  •  21
    Meaning and semantics
    In Milton Karl Munitz & Peter K. Unger (eds.), Semantics and philosophy: [essays], New York University Press. 1974.
  • Meaning and semantics
    In Milton Karl Munitz & Peter K. Unger (eds.), Semantics and philosophy: [essays], New York University Press. 1974.
  •  59
  •  98
    Character
    with Maria Merritt and John Doris
    In John Doris (ed.), Moral Psychology Handbook, Oxford University Press. 2010.
  •  1
  •  19
    Conceptual role semantics
    In Ernie Lepore & Barry C. Smith (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Language, Oxford University Press. pp. 295. 2005.
    CRS says that the meanings of expressions of a language or other symbol system or the contents of mental states are determined and explained by the way symbols are used in thinking. According to CRS one
  •  8
    Introduction
    In Reasoning, meaning, and mind, Oxford University Press. 1999.
  •  504
    (Nonsolipsistic) conceptual role semantics
    In Ernest LePore (ed.), New directions in semantics, Academic Press. 1987.
    CRS says that the meanings of expressions of a language or other symbol system or the contents of mental states are determined and explained by the way symbols are used in thinking. According to CRS one
  •  7
    There are two approaches to the understanding of the experiences and uses of language of others. One emphasizes translation. The other restricts itself to an objective description of use and function. Each approach by itself must leave something out. We need both approaches.
  •  10
    The Death of Meaning
    In Reasoning, meaning, and mind, Oxford University Press. 1999.
    Provides a sympathetic account of Quine's rejection of analyticity, language‐independent meanings, and other intensional objects. Explains Quine's thesis of the indeterminacy of radical translation in terms of the example of various ways to translate number theory to set theory. Elaborates a positive Quinean theory of meaning, which puts weight on translation, where translation is not a strict equivalence relation.
  •  10
    A response to a paper by Frank Jackson. Although philosophers sometimes defend certain ‘analyses’ as analytic or a priori truths, such analyses are far from obviously true and are defended inductively. Contrary to Jackson's claim, the rejection of analyticity is based on consideration of central cases.
  •  8
    Three Levels of Meaning
    In Reasoning, meaning, and mind, Oxford University Press. 1999.
    Three conceptions of meaning of meaning can be distinguished — meaning as conceptual role, meaning as communicated thought and meaning as speech‐act potential. At one time, these were conceived as competing conceptions, but it is better to see them as potentially compatible theories that are concerned with different aspects or levels of meaning.
  •  89
    Analogies are often theoretically useful. Important principles of electricity are suggested by an analogy between water current flowing through a pipe and electrical current “flowing” through a wire. A basic theory of sound is suggested by an analogy between waves caused by a stone being dropped into a still lake and “sound waves” caused by a disturbance in air.
  •  151
    Language, thought, and communication
    Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 7 270-298. 1975.
    Consider the idea that a natural language like English is in the first instance incorporated into the system of representation one thinks with. This ‘incorporation’ view is compared with a translation or ‘decoding’ view of communication. Compositional semantics makes sense only given the implausible decoding view.
  • Moral Relativism and Moral Objectivity
    Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 50 (4): 654-658. 1996.
  •  3
    Moral Relativism and Moral Objectivity
    Philosophical Quarterly 48 (192): 387-390. 1998.
  •  3
    Moral Relativism and Moral Objectivity
    Noûs 33 (2): 295-303. 1999.
  •  31
    Reasons
    Critica 7 (21): 3-17. 1975.
  •  8
    Wide Functionalism
    In Reasoning, meaning, and mind, Oxford University Press. 1999.
    Psychological explanation is a kind of functional explanation, like some biological explanation, where the relevant functions tend to have to do with perceiving and acting in relation to the environment. Pain serves as a kind of alarm system; perception allows an organism to get information about the environment etc. Although there are defenders of a narrow, more solipsistic psychological functionalism, the dominant trend has involved the wider version. In any event, the wider functionalism is c…Read more
  •  18
    Replies to three related arguments against wide functionalism. The first says that we are directly aware of intrinsic features of our experience and points out that there is no way to account for such an awareness in a purely functional view. The second claims that a person blind from birth can know all about the functional role of visual experience without knowing what it is like to see something red. The third holds that functionalism cannot account for the possibility of an inverted spectrum.…Read more
  •  9
    Simplicity is used in curve‐fitting and can be illustrated by Goodman's ‘new riddle of induction.’ Taking the simplicity of a hypothesis to depend entirely on the simplicity of the way it is represented does not work, because simplicity of representation is too dependent on the method of representation, and any hypothesis can be represented simply. An alternative ‘semantic’ theory also has problems. A ‘computational’ theory is defended that considers how easy it is to use a hypothesis to get ans…Read more
  •  8
    Rationality
    In Reasoning, meaning, and mind, Oxford University Press. 1999.
    Distinguishes logic from the theory of reasoning, rejects special epistemic foundations in favour of a general epistemological conservatism and discusses the role in reasoning of coherence and simplicity. The difference between theoretical and practical reasoning is discussed, as is the role that practical considerations play in theoretical reasoning.
  •  5
    Practical Reasoning
    In Reasoning, meaning, and mind, Oxford University Press. 1999.
    Intentions are distinct real psychological states, not mere constructs out of beliefs and desires. One intends to do something only if one believes one will do it. Positive intentions are to be distinguished from negative and conditional intentions. All intentions are self‐referential and are to be distinguished from beliefs by means of differences between theoretical reasoning, which directly modifies beliefs, and practical reasoning, which directly modifies intentions. One can sometimes adopt …Read more
  •  8
    Discusses how to explain the distinction between epistemic and non‐epistemic reasons while allowing epistemic reasons to be affected by pragmatic considerations of simplicity, coherence, and conservatism. After noting difficulties with trying to explain epistemic reasons in terms of connections with truth or the goal of believing what is true, the chapter discusses issues about the nature of probability, suggesting that epistemic reasons connect with conditional probability in a way that non‐epi…Read more
  •  8
    Consider the idea that a natural language like English is in the first instance incorporated into the system of representation one thinks with. This ‘incorporation’ view is compared with a translation or ‘decoding’ view of communication. Compositional semantics makes sense only given the implausible decoding view.