• PhilPeople
  • PhilPapers
  • PhilArchive
  • PhilEvents
  • PhilJobs
  • Sign in
PhilPeople
 
  • Sign in
  • News Feed
  • Find Philosophers
  • Departments
  • Radar
  • Help
 

Drag to reposition

Grace Helton
Princeton University
  •  Home
  •  Publications
    4
    • Most Recent
    • Most Downloaded
    • Topics
  •  Recommended
    9
  •  Events
    4
  •  News and Updates
    8

 More details
  • Princeton University
    Department of Philosophy
    Assistant Professor
Homepage
Princeton, New Jersey, United States of America
0000-0003-3729-5415
Areas of Specialization
The Experience of High-Level Properties
Epistemic Norms
Ought Implies Can
Belief Theories of Perception
The Nature of Belief
Illusion and Hallucination
Perception and Thought
Perception and the Mind
Science of Perception
Ethics of Belief
5 more
Areas of Interest
Skepticism
The Problem of Other Minds
Social Epistemology
Gender and Oppression
Racism and Psychology
Philosophical Progress
Introspection and Introspectionism
2 more
  • All publications (4)
  •  769
    If You Can't Change What You Believe, You Don't Believe It
    Noûs 54 (3): 501-526. 2020.
    I develop and defend the view that subjects are necessarily psychologically able to revise their beliefs in response to relevant counter-evidence. Specifically, subjects can revise their beliefs in response to relevant counter-evidence, given their current psychological mechanisms and skills. If a subject lacks this ability, then the mental state in question is not a belief, though it may be some other kind of cognitive attitude, such as a supposi-tion, an entertained thought, or a pretense. The…Read more
    I develop and defend the view that subjects are necessarily psychologically able to revise their beliefs in response to relevant counter-evidence. Specifically, subjects can revise their beliefs in response to relevant counter-evidence, given their current psychological mechanisms and skills. If a subject lacks this ability, then the mental state in question is not a belief, though it may be some other kind of cognitive attitude, such as a supposi-tion, an entertained thought, or a pretense. The result is a moderately revisionary view of belief: while most mental states we thought were beliefs are beliefs, some mental states which we thought were beliefs are not beliefs. The argument for this view draws on two key claims: First, subjects are rationally obligated to revise their beliefs in response to relevant counter-evidence. Second, if some subject is rationally obligated to revise one of her mental states, then that subject can revise that mental state, given her current psychological mechanisms and skills. Along the way to defending these claims, I argue that rational obligations can govern activities which reflect on one’s rational character, whether or not those activities are under one’s voluntary control. I also show how the relevant version of epistemic ‘ought’ implies ‘can’ survives an objection which plagues other variants of the principle.
    Epistemic ValueDoxastic VoluntarismEthics of BeliefBelief Revision, MiscThe Nature of BeliefOught Im…Read more
    Epistemic ValueDoxastic VoluntarismEthics of BeliefBelief Revision, MiscThe Nature of BeliefOught Implies CanEpistemic Normativity, MiscDelusionsTacit and Dispositional BeliefEpistemic NormsImplicit Bias
  •  754
    Recent Issues in High-Level Perception
    Philosophy Compass 11 (12): 851-862. 2016.
    Recently, several theorists have proposed that we can perceive a range of high-level features, including natural kind features (e.g., being a lemur), artifactual features (e.g., being a mandolin), and the emotional features of others (e.g., being surprised). I clarify the claim that we perceive high-level features and suggest one overlooked reason this claim matters: it would dramatically expand the range of actions perception-based theories of action might explain. I then describe the influenti…Read more
    Recently, several theorists have proposed that we can perceive a range of high-level features, including natural kind features (e.g., being a lemur), artifactual features (e.g., being a mandolin), and the emotional features of others (e.g., being surprised). I clarify the claim that we perceive high-level features and suggest one overlooked reason this claim matters: it would dramatically expand the range of actions perception-based theories of action might explain. I then describe the influential phenomenal contrast method of arguing for high-level perception and discuss some of the objections that have been raised against this strategy. Finally, I describe two emerging defenses of high-level perception, one of which appeals to a certain class of perceptual deficits and one of which appeals to adaptation effects. I sketch a challenge for the latter approach.
    Perception and PhenomenologyPerception and ThoughtTopics in the Philosophy of Gender, MiscScience of…Read more
    Perception and PhenomenologyPerception and ThoughtTopics in the Philosophy of Gender, MiscScience of Visual ConsciousnessThe Experience of High-Level PropertiesPerceptual ReportsThe Experience of ObjectsThe Nature of Perceptual ExperienceThe Contents of Perception, MiscFoundationalismPerception and ActionSeemings
  •  427
    Visually Perceiving the Intentions of Others
    Philosophical Quarterly 68 (271): 243-264. 2018.
    I argue that we sometimes visually perceive the intentions of others. Just as we can see something as blue or as moving to the left, so too can we see someone as intending to evade detection or as aiming to traverse a physical obstacle. I consider the typical subject presented with the Heider and Simmel movie, a widely studied ‘animacy’ stimulus, and I argue that this subject mentally attributes proximal intentions to some of the objects in the movie. I further argue that these attributions are …Read more
    I argue that we sometimes visually perceive the intentions of others. Just as we can see something as blue or as moving to the left, so too can we see someone as intending to evade detection or as aiming to traverse a physical obstacle. I consider the typical subject presented with the Heider and Simmel movie, a widely studied ‘animacy’ stimulus, and I argue that this subject mentally attributes proximal intentions to some of the objects in the movie. I further argue that these attributions are unrevisable in a certain sense and that this result can be used to as part of an argument that these attributions are not post-perceptual thoughts. Finally, I suggest that if these attributions are visual experiences, and more particularly visual illusions, their unrevisability can be satisfyingly explained, by appealing to the mechanisms which underlie visual illusions more generally.
    Intentional ActionPerception and PhenomenologyThe Experience of High-Level PropertiesIllusion and Ha…Read more
    Intentional ActionPerception and PhenomenologyThe Experience of High-Level PropertiesIllusion and HallucinationPerception and ThoughtMindreadingThe Nature of IntentionIntention and KnowledgeAspects of IntentionalitySeemingsDirect Knowledge and Other MindsIntentions, Misc
  •  364
    Amodal completion and knowledge
    with Bence Nanay
    Analysis 79 (3): 415-423. 2019.
    Amodal completion is the representation of occluded parts of perceived objects. We argue for the following three claims: First, at least some amodal completion-involved experiences can ground knowledge about the occluded portions of perceived objects. Second, at least some instances of amodal completion-grounded knowledge are not sensitive, that is, it is not the case that in the nearest worlds in which the relevant claim is false, that claim is not believed true. Third, at least some instances …Read more
    Amodal completion is the representation of occluded parts of perceived objects. We argue for the following three claims: First, at least some amodal completion-involved experiences can ground knowledge about the occluded portions of perceived objects. Second, at least some instances of amodal completion-grounded knowledge are not sensitive, that is, it is not the case that in the nearest worlds in which the relevant claim is false, that claim is not believed true. Third, at least some instances of amodal completion-grounded knowledge are not safe, that is, it is not the case that in all or nearly all near worlds where the relevant claim is believed true, that claim is in fact true. Thus, certain instances of amodal completion-grounded knowledge refute both the view that knowledge is necessarily sensitive and the view that knowledge is necessarily safe.
    FoundationalismPerceptual JustificationSafety and SensitivityThe Experience of ObjectsPhilosophy of …Read more
    FoundationalismPerceptual JustificationSafety and SensitivityThe Experience of ObjectsPhilosophy of PsychologyScience of Visual Consciousness, MiscEpistemological Sources, MiscNaturalized EpistemologyPerceptual EvidenceMental States, Misc
PhilPeople logo

On this site

  • Find a philosopher
  • Find a department
  • The Radar
  • Index of professional philosophers
  • Index of departments
  • Help
  • Acknowledgments
  • Careers
  • Contact us
  • Terms and conditions

Brought to you by

  • The PhilPapers Foundation
  • The American Philosophical Association
  • Centre for Digital Philosophy, Western University
PhilPeople is currently in Beta Sponsored by the PhilPapers Foundation and the American Philosophical Association
Feedback