•  2
    Singular Causation and Law
    PSA Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1990 (1): 537-543. 1990.
    Humean accounts of law are at the same time accounts of causation. Accordingly, since laws of nature are nothing but contingent cosmic regularities, to be a cause is just to be an instance of such a law. It follows from this view that it is logically impossible that there be causally related events which are not law-governed. Any particular cause-effect pair instantiates some law of nature, where the law is understood as a regularity. The regularity itself may be understood phenomenalistically, …Read more
  •  3
    Causal Modeling and the Statistical Analysis of Causation
    PSA Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1986 (1): 12-23. 1986.
    Recent studies on probabilistic causation and statistical explanation (Cartwright 1979; Salmon 1984), I believe, have opened up the possibility of a genuine unification between philosophical approaches and causal modeling (CM) in the social, behavioral and biological sciences (Wright 1934; Blalock 1964; Asher 1976). This unification rests on the statistical tools employed, the principle of common cause, the irreducibility of causation to probability or statistics, and the idea of causal process …Read more
  •  1576
    What Is Epistemic Public Trust in Science?
    with Faik Kurtulmuş
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 70 (4): 1145-1166. 2019.
    We provide an analysis of the public's having warranted epistemic trust in science, that is, the conditions under which the public may be said to have well-placed trust in the scientists as providers of information. We distinguish between basic and enhanced epistemic trust in science and provide necessary conditions for both. We then present the controversy regarding the connection between autism and measles–mumps–rubella vaccination as a case study to illustrate our analysis. The realization of…Read more
  •  1236
    Distributive Epistemic Justice in Science
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. 2021.
    This article develops an account of distributive epistemic justice in the production of scientific knowledge. We identify four requirements: (a) science should produce the knowledge citizens need in order to reason about the common good, their individual good and pursuit thereof; (b) science should produce the knowledge those serving the public need to pursue justice effectively; (c) science should be organized in such a way that it does not aid the wilful manufacturing of ignorance; and (d) whe…Read more
  •  37
    This Introduction to the Special Issue on “Responsible Research and Innovation” outlines features of the philosophical debate about the concepts involved and summarizes the papers assembled in this issue. The topic of RRI is widely discussed in science studies and has made its way into science policy. This SI is intended to make the contributions of philosophers of science more visible. The philosophically relevant parts of the field concern, among others, the processes of public participation i…Read more
  •  125
    The papers collected in this Synthese special issue are the result of a conference that one of us (ES) casually suggested and the other (GI) organized, which took place at Bo˘gaziçi University in Istanbul, in May 2008, to commemorate the seventieth anniversary of the publication of Experience and Prediction. These papers are historical and philosophical in varying degrees. Reichenbach is now often lumped together with the logical positivists of the Vienna Circle, but his ideas, especially those …Read more
  •  598
    Well-ordered science and public trust in science
    Synthese 198 (Suppl 19): 4731-4748. 2021.
    Building, restoring and maintaining well-placed trust between scientists and the public is a difficult yet crucial social task requiring the successful cooperation of various social actors and institutions. Kitcher’s takes up this challenge in the context of liberal democratic societies by extending his ideal model of “well-ordered science” that he had originally formulated in his. However, Kitcher nowhere offers an explicit account of what it means for the public to invest epistemic trust in sc…Read more
  •  23
    Worldviews and their relation to science
    Science & Education 18 (6-7): 729-745. 2009.
  •  28
    Kuhn, Carnap, and logical empiricism
    with Irzık Gürol
    In Thomas Uebel (ed.), The Handbook of Logical Empiricism, Routledge. forthcoming.
    According to the conventional wisdom, Thomas Kuhn’s Structure of Scientific Revolutions played a major role in the demise of logical empiricism by demolishing its key tenets and replacing them with an alternative picture of science that has virtually nothing in common with them. However, the relationship between Kuhn’s views and LE is not at all as straightforward as this claim suggests. While is undoubtedly correct, the revisionist historiography of LE in the last two-and-a-half decades documen…Read more
  • Logical Empiricism
    University of Pittsburgh Press. 2003.
  •  76
    Incredulity towards Lyotard: a critique of a postmodernist account of science and knowledg
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 34 (2): 391-421. 2003.
    Philosophers of science have paid little attention, positive or negative, to Lyotard’s book The postmodern condition, even though it has been popular in other fields. We set out some of the reasons for this neglect. Lyotard thought that sciences could be justified by non-scientific narratives. We show why this is unacceptable, and why many of Lyotard’s characterisations of science are either implausible or are narrowly positivist. One of Lyotard’s themes is that the nature of knowledge has chang…Read more
  •  131
    Whorfian variations on Kantian themes: Kuhn's linguistic turn
    with Teo Grünberg
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 29 (2): 207-221. 1998.
    Thomas Kuhn's post-1980 writings have increasingly emphasized the role played by language in the characterization of scientific revolutions and incommensurability. We argue that Kuhn's `linguistic turn' can be understood best against the background of a Whorfian conception of language and certain neo-Kantian themes. While this enables Kuhn to refine and unify his earlier views, it also creates some difficulties.
  •  18
    Volume Introduction
    with Stephen Voss and Berna Kilinç
    The Proceedings of the Twenty-First World Congress of Philosophy 5 11-13. 2007.
  • Which multiculturalism?
    with Irzik Sibel
    Science & Education 11 (4). 2002.
  •  149
    Singular Causation and Law
    PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1990. 1990.
    Humean accounts of law are at the same time accounts of causation. Accordingly, since laws are nothing but contingent cosmic regularities, to be a cause is just to be an instance of such a law. Every particular cause-effect pair, according to these accounts, instantiates some law of nature. I argue that this claim is false. Singular causation without being governed by any law is logically and physically possible. Separating causes from laws enables us to see the distinct role each plays in scien…Read more
  •  23
    2 Kuhn and Logical Positivism
    In Vasō Kintē & Theodore Arabatzis (eds.), Kuhn's The structure of scientific revolutions revisited, Routledge. pp. 15. 2012.
  •  257
    Can causes be reduced to correlations?
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 47 (2): 249-270. 1996.
    This paper argues against Papineau's claim that causal relations can be reduced to correlations and defends Cartwright's thesis that they can be nevertheless boot-strapped from them, given sufficiently rich causal background knowledge.
  • Arda Denkel Anısına yazılar
    Felsefe Tartismalari 27 9-28. 2000.
  •  15
    Which multiculturalism?
    with Sibel Irzik
    Science & Education 11 (4): 393-403. 2002.
  •  454
    Justice in the Distribution of Knowledge
    Episteme 14 (2): 129-146. 2017.
    In this article we develop an account of justice in the distribution of knowledge. We first argue that knowledge is a fundamental interest that grounds claims of justice due to its role in individuals’ deliberations about the common good, their personal good and the pursuit thereof. Second, we identify the epistemic basic structure of a society, namely, the institutions that determine individuals’ opportunities for acquiring knowledge and discuss what justice requires of them. Our main contentio…Read more
  •  54
    Human Needs, Consumption, and Social Policy
    with Ayşe Buğra
    Economics and Philosophy 15 (2): 187. 1999.
    From its early origins to the present, the development of mainstream economic theory has taken a direction which has excluded the analysis of human needs as a basis for social policy. The problems associated with this orientation are increasingly recognized both by economists and non-economists. As Sen points out, it is indeed strange for a discipline concerned with the well-being of people to neglect the question of needs. Currently, some writers such as Doyal and Gough, post-Keynesian economis…Read more
  •  13
    Drawing on the recent revisionary scholarship regarding logical positivism and its relation to the early post-positivism, I display and question the standard historical understanding of the analytical philosophy of science from the late 1920s to the mid-1970s. I then propose an alternative account based on the internal-external distinction. I conclude by showing some advantages of my alternative narrative that does more justice to the logical positivism than the standard understanding and sugges…Read more
  •  24
  • Changing Conceptions of Rationality
    In Paolo Parrini, Wes Salmon & Merrilee Salmon (eds.), Logical Empiricism: Historical and Contemporary Perspectives, Pittsburgh University Pres. pp. 325. 2003.