•  1576
    What Is Epistemic Public Trust in Science?
    with Faik Kurtulmuş
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 70 (4): 1145-1166. 2019.
    We provide an analysis of the public's having warranted epistemic trust in science, that is, the conditions under which the public may be said to have well-placed trust in the scientists as providers of information. We distinguish between basic and enhanced epistemic trust in science and provide necessary conditions for both. We then present the controversy regarding the connection between autism and measles–mumps–rubella vaccination as a case study to illustrate our analysis. The realization of…Read more
  •  1236
    Distributive Epistemic Justice in Science
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. 2021.
    This article develops an account of distributive epistemic justice in the production of scientific knowledge. We identify four requirements: (a) science should produce the knowledge citizens need in order to reason about the common good, their individual good and pursuit thereof; (b) science should produce the knowledge those serving the public need to pursue justice effectively; (c) science should be organized in such a way that it does not aid the wilful manufacturing of ignorance; and (d) whe…Read more
  •  598
    Well-ordered science and public trust in science
    Synthese 198 (Suppl 19): 4731-4748. 2021.
    Building, restoring and maintaining well-placed trust between scientists and the public is a difficult yet crucial social task requiring the successful cooperation of various social actors and institutions. Kitcher’s takes up this challenge in the context of liberal democratic societies by extending his ideal model of “well-ordered science” that he had originally formulated in his. However, Kitcher nowhere offers an explicit account of what it means for the public to invest epistemic trust in sc…Read more
  •  454
    Justice in the Distribution of Knowledge
    Episteme 14 (2): 129-146. 2017.
    In this article we develop an account of justice in the distribution of knowledge. We first argue that knowledge is a fundamental interest that grounds claims of justice due to its role in individuals’ deliberations about the common good, their personal good and the pursuit thereof. Second, we identify the epistemic basic structure of a society, namely, the institutions that determine individuals’ opportunities for acquiring knowledge and discuss what justice requires of them. Our main contentio…Read more
  •  257
    Can causes be reduced to correlations?
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 47 (2): 249-270. 1996.
    This paper argues against Papineau's claim that causal relations can be reduced to correlations and defends Cartwright's thesis that they can be nevertheless boot-strapped from them, given sufficiently rich causal background knowledge.
  •  184
    Carnap and Kuhn: Arch enemies or close allies?
    with Teo Grünberg
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 46 (3): 285-307. 1995.
    We compare Carnap's and Kuhn's views on science. Although there are important differences between them, the similarities are striking. The basis for the latter is a pragmatically oriented semantic conventionalist picture of science, which suggests that the view that post-positivist philosophy of science constitutes a radical revolution which has no interesting affinities with logical positivism must be seriously mistaken.
  •  149
    Singular Causation and Law
    PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1990. 1990.
    Humean accounts of law are at the same time accounts of causation. Accordingly, since laws are nothing but contingent cosmic regularities, to be a cause is just to be an instance of such a law. Every particular cause-effect pair, according to these accounts, instantiates some law of nature. I argue that this claim is false. Singular causation without being governed by any law is logically and physically possible. Separating causes from laws enables us to see the distinct role each plays in scien…Read more
  •  137
    The idea of family resemblance, when applied to science, can provide a powerful account of the nature of science (NOS). In this chapter we develop such an account by taking into consideration the consensus on NOS that emerged in the science education literature in the last decade or so. According to the family resemblance approach, the nature of science can be systematically and comprehensively characterised in terms of a number of science categories which exhibit strong similarities and overlap…Read more
  •  133
    A Family Resemblance Approach to the Nature of Science for Science Education
    with Gurol Irzik and Robert Nola
    Science & Education 20 (7-8): 591-607. 2011.
    Although there is universal consensus both in the science education literature and in the science standards documents to the effect that students should learn not only the content of science but also its nature, there is little agreement about what that nature is. This led many science educators to adopt what is sometimes called “the consensus view” about the nature of science (NOS), whose goal is to teach students only those characteristics of science on which there is wide consensus. This is a…Read more
  •  131
    Whorfian variations on Kantian themes: Kuhn's linguistic turn
    with Teo Grünberg
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 29 (2): 207-221. 1998.
    Thomas Kuhn's post-1980 writings have increasingly emphasized the role played by language in the characterization of scientific revolutions and incommensurability. We argue that Kuhn's `linguistic turn' can be understood best against the background of a Whorfian conception of language and certain neo-Kantian themes. While this enables Kuhn to refine and unify his earlier views, it also creates some difficulties.
  •  125
    The papers collected in this Synthese special issue are the result of a conference that one of us (ES) casually suggested and the other (GI) organized, which took place at Bo˘gaziçi University in Istanbul, in May 2008, to commemorate the seventieth anniversary of the publication of Experience and Prediction. These papers are historical and philosophical in varying degrees. Reichenbach is now often lumped together with the logical positivists of the Vienna Circle, but his ideas, especially those …Read more
  •  117
    Back to Basics: A Philosophical Critique of Constructivism
    Studies in Philosophy and Education 20 (2): 157-175. 2001.
  •  112
    Hans Reichenbach in Istanbul
    Synthese 181 (1). 2011.
    Fleeing from the Nazi regime, along with many German refugees, Hans Reichenbach came to teach at Istanbul University in 1933, accepting the invitation of the Turkish government and stayed in Istanbul until 1938. While much is known about his work and life in Istanbul, the existing literature relies mostly on his letters and works. In this article I try to shed more light on Reichenbach's scholarly activities and personal life by also taking into account the Turkish sources and the academic conte…Read more
  •  87
    Causal modeling: New directions for statistical explanation
    with Eric Meyer
    Philosophy of Science 54 (4): 495-514. 1987.
    Causal modeling methods such as path analysis, used in the social and natural sciences, are also highly relevant to philosophical problems of probabilistic causation and statistical explanation. We show how these methods can be effectively used (1) to improve and extend Salmon's S-R basis for statistical explanation, and (2) to repair Cartwright's resolution of Simpson's paradox, clarifying the relationship between statistical and causal claims
  •  76
    Incredulity towards Lyotard: a critique of a postmodernist account of science and knowledg
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 34 (2): 391-421. 2003.
    Philosophers of science have paid little attention, positive or negative, to Lyotard’s book The postmodern condition, even though it has been popular in other fields. We set out some of the reasons for this neglect. Lyotard thought that sciences could be justified by non-scientific narratives. We show why this is unacceptable, and why many of Lyotard’s characterisations of science are either implausible or are narrowly positivist. One of Lyotard’s themes is that the nature of knowledge has chang…Read more
  •  74
    Volume Introduction
    The Proceedings of the Twenty-First World Congress of Philosophy 5 11-13. 2007.
  •  58
    Probabilistic Metaphysics (review)
    Teaching Philosophy 9 (2): 178-180. 1986.
  •  57
    Science and its Discontents
    The Proceedings of the Twenty-First World Congress of Philosophy 13 147-161. 2007.
  •  54
    Human Needs, Consumption, and Social Policy
    with Ayşe Buğra
    Economics and Philosophy 15 (2): 187. 1999.
    From its early origins to the present, the development of mainstream economic theory has taken a direction which has excluded the analysis of human needs as a basis for social policy. The problems associated with this orientation are increasingly recognized both by economists and non-economists. As Sen points out, it is indeed strange for a discipline concerned with the well-being of people to neglect the question of needs. Currently, some writers such as Doyal and Gough, post-Keynesian economis…Read more
  •  37
    This Introduction to the Special Issue on “Responsible Research and Innovation” outlines features of the philosophical debate about the concepts involved and summarizes the papers assembled in this issue. The topic of RRI is widely discussed in science studies and has made its way into science policy. This SI is intended to make the contributions of philosophers of science more visible. The philosophically relevant parts of the field concern, among others, the processes of public participation i…Read more
  •  28
    Causal Modeling and the Statistical Analysis of Causation
    PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1986. 1986.
    Recent philosophical studies of probabilistic causation and statistical explanation have opened up the possibility of unifying philosophical approaches with causal modeling as practiced in the social and biological sciences. This unification rests upon the statistical tools employed, the principle of common cause, the irreducibility of causation to statistics, and the idea of causal process as a suitable framework for understanding causal relationships. These four areas of contact are discussed …Read more
  •  28
    Introduction: Commercialization of Academic Science and a New Agenda for Science Education
    with Gurol Irzik
    Science & Education 22 (10): 2375-2384. 2013.
    Certain segments of science are becoming increasingly commercialized. This article discusses the commercialization of academic science and its impact on various aspects of science. It also aims to provide an introduction to the articles in this special issue. I briefly describe the major factors that led to this phenomenon, situate it in the context of the changing social regime of science and give a thumbnail sketch of its costs and benefits. I close with a general discussion of how the topic o…Read more
  •  28
    Kuhn, Carnap, and logical empiricism
    with Irzık Gürol
    In Thomas Uebel (ed.), The Handbook of Logical Empiricism, Routledge. forthcoming.
    According to the conventional wisdom, Thomas Kuhn’s Structure of Scientific Revolutions played a major role in the demise of logical empiricism by demolishing its key tenets and replacing them with an alternative picture of science that has virtually nothing in common with them. However, the relationship between Kuhn’s views and LE is not at all as straightforward as this claim suggests. While is undoubtedly correct, the revisionist historiography of LE in the last two-and-a-half decades documen…Read more
  •  26
    Turkish Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science (edited book)
    with Güven Güzeldere
    Springer. 2005.
    The book also contains an unpublished interview with Maria Reichenbach, Hans Reichenbach's wife, which sheds new light on Reichenbach's academic and personal ...
  •  24
  •  23
    2 Kuhn and Logical Positivism
    In Vasō Kintē & Theodore Arabatzis (eds.), Kuhn's The structure of scientific revolutions revisited, Routledge. pp. 15. 2012.