•  81
    My objective is a better comprehension of two theoretically fundamental concepts. One, the concept of a substance in an ordinary (non-Aristotelian) sense, ranging over such things as salt, carbon, copper, iron, water, and methane – kinds of stuff that now count as (chemical) elements and compounds. The other I’ll call the object-concept in the abstract sense of    Russell, Wittgenstein, and Frege in their logico-semantical enquiries. The material object-concept constitutes the heart of our recei…Read more
  •  654
    Any Sum of Parts which are Water is Water
    Humana Mente 4 (19): 41-55. 2011.
    Mereological entities often seem to violate ‘ordinary’ ideas of what a concrete object can be like, behaving more like sets than like Aristotelian substances. However, the mereological notions of ‘part’, ‘composition’, and ‘sum’ or ‘fusion’ appear to find concrete realisation in the actual semantics of mass nouns. Quine notes that ‘any sum of parts which are water is water’; and the wine from a single barrel can be distributed around the globe without affecting its identity. Is there here, as so…Read more
  •  31
    Words without Objects
    Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 2 (2): 147-182. 1998.
    Resolution of the problem of mass nouns depends on an expansion of our semantic/ontological taxonomy. Semantically, mass nouns are neither singular nor plural; they apply to neither just one object, nor to many objects, at a time. But their deepest kinship links them to the plural. A plural phrase — 'the cats in Kingston' — does not denote a single plural thing, but merely many distinct things. Just so, 'the water in the lake' does not denote a single aggregate — it is not ONE, but rather MUCH. …Read more
  •  46
    Ordinary Language and Materialism
    Philosophy 42 (162). 1967.
    The concept of 'the body', in the supposed contrast of mind and body, is not to be distinguished from the concept of the person, hence dualism is an incorrect conception of the supposed contrast, which is consistent with some form of materialism.
  •  35
    Critical Notice of Rom Harré and Paul. E. Secord, The Explanation of Social Behaviour (review)
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 5 (1): 173-180. 1975.
  •  33
    The Structure of Marx's World-View (review)
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 15 (3): 553-563. 1985.
  •  7
    Istvan Meszaros, The Power of Ideology Reviewed by
    Philosophy in Review 11 (3): 214-216. 1991.
  •  13
    Critical notice
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 15 (3): 553-563. 1985.
  •  1058
    A picture of the world as chiefly one of discrete objects, distributed in space and time, has sometimes seemed compelling. It is however one of the main targets of Henry Laycock's book; for it is seriously incomplete. The picture, he argues, leaves no space for "stuff" like air and water. With discrete objects, we may always ask "how many?," but with stuff the question has to be "how much?" Laycock's fascinating exploration also addresses key logical and linguistic questions about the way we cat…Read more
  • Language
    “The Language of Science” (ISSN Code. 2007.
    I offer a synoptic account of some chief parameters of language and its relationship to communication and to thought, distinguishing in the process between semantical and pragmatic dimensions of utterance.
  •  21
    Time, Language, and Ontology: The World from the B-Theoretic Perspective (review)
    Review of Metaphysics 69 (3): 630-632. 2016.
  •  32
    Exploitation and Equality: Labour Power as a Non-Commodity
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary Volume 15 (sup1): 375-389. 1989.
    The theory of surplus value contrasts ‘pay for labour power’ and ‘pay for labour services’. Unlike labour services but like all commodities, labour power has a specific economic value and it exchanges at this value. Unlike that of other commodities, the consumption of labour power results in the creation of more value than the commodity itself contains. Surplus value arises from the gap between the labour needed to sustain a day’s work, to keep the worker going for a day, and the labour performe…Read more
  •  307
    Variables, generality and existence
    In Paulo Valore (ed.), Topics on General and Formal Ontology, Polimetrica. pp. 27. 2006.
    So-called mass nouns, however precisely they are defined, are in any case a subset of non-count nouns. Count nouns are either singular or plural; to be non-count is hence to be neither singular nor plural. This is not, as such, a metaphysically significant contrast: 'pieces of furniture' is plural whereas 'furniture' itself is non-count. This contrast is simply between 'the many / few' and 'the much / little' - between counting and measuring. However not all non-count nouns are, like 'furniture'…Read more
  •  23
    Jean Hyppolite, Studies on Marx and Hegel (review)
    Dialogue 9 (2): 248-250. 1970.
  • Istvan Meszaros, The Power of Ideology (review)
    Philosophy in Review 11 214-216. 1991.
  •  89
    Critical notice, G. A. Cohen, Marx's Theory of History (review)
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 10 (2): 335-356. 1980.
    Mills writes: G. A. Cohen's influential ‘technological determinist’ reading of Marx's theory of history rests in part on an interpretation of Marx's use of ‘material’ whose idiosyncrasy has been insufficiently noticed. Cohen takes historical materialism to be asserting the determination of the social by the material/asocial, viz. ‘socio‐neutral’ facts about human nature and human rationality which manifest themselves in a historical tendency for the forces of production to develop. This paper re…Read more
  •  16
  •  245
    Object
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2010.
    In The Principles of Mathematics, Russell writes: Whatever may be an object of thought, or may occur in any true or false proposition, or can be counted as one, I call a term. This, then, is the widest word in the philosophical vocabulary. I shall use as synonymous with it the words unit, individual and entity. The first two emphasize the fact that every term is one, while the third is derived from the fact that every term has being, i.e. is in some sense. A man, a moment, a number, a class, a r…Read more
  •  5
    Exploitation and Equality: Labour Power as a Non-Commodity
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary Volume 15 (n/a): 375-389. 1989.
    The theory of surplus value contrasts ‘pay for labour power’ and ‘pay for labour services’. Unlike labour services but like all commodities, labour power has a specific economic value and it exchanges at this value. Unlike that of other commodities, the consumption of labour power results in the creation of more value than the commodity itself contains. Surplus value arises from the gap between the labour needed to sustain a day’s work, to keep the worker going for a day, and the labour performe…Read more
  •  6
    Barry Barnes, The Nature of Power Reviewed by
    Philosophy in Review 9 (10): 394-396. 1989.
  •  76
    Matter and Objecthood Disentangled
    Dialogue 28 (1): 17-. 1989.
    The concept of matter is not, I urge, reducible to the concept of an object. This is to be distingusihed from the counterintuitive Aristotelian claim that matter depends for its existence on objects which it constitutes.
  •  11
    Critical notice
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 5 (1): 173-180. 1975.
  •  2
    Alan Garfinkel, Forms of Explanation (review)
    Philosophy in Review 2 93-96. 1982.