•  6
    L
    In Samuel Guttenplan (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind, Blackwell. 2017.
    The Representational Theory of the Mind arises with the recognition that thoughts have contents carried by mental representations. For Abelard to think, for example, that Pegasus is winged is for Abelard to be related to a MENTAL REPRESENTATION whose content is that Pegasus is winged. Now, there are different kinds of representations: pictures, maps, models, and words ‐ to name only some. Exactly what sort of REPRESENTATION is mental representation? (see imagery; connectionism.) Sententialism di…Read more
  •  15
    J. Christopher Maloney argues that free will is compatible with necessary laws of science and immutable history. For free will emerges from an akratic will that asymptotically approaches the ability to choose to act otherwise than it willfully does.
  •  22
    Knowledge and the Flow of Information
    Noûs 19 (2): 299-306. 1985.
  •  59
    Information, Semantics & Epistemology (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 53 (3): 721-726. 1993.
  •  12
    Thought, including conscious perception, is representation. But perceptual representation is uniquely direct, permitting immediate acquaintance with the world and ensuring perception's distinctive phenomenal character. The perceptive mind is extended. It recruits the very objects perceived to constitute self-referential representations determinative of what it is like to perceive.
  •  53
  •  36
    A theory of perception
    American Philosophical Quarterly 18 (1): 63-70. 1981.
  •  73
    The mundane mental language: How to do words with things
    Synthese 59 (June): 251-294. 1984.
  •  20
    The Mundane Matter of the Mental Language
    Philosophical Quarterly 41 (162): 106-109. 1991.
  •  134
    The right stuff
    Synthese 70 (March): 349-72. 1987.
  •  133
    Methodological solipsism reconsidered as a research strategy in cognitive psychology
    Philosophy of Science 52 (September): 451-69. 1985.
    Current computational psychology, especially as described by Fodor (1975, 1980, 1981), Pylyshyn (1980), and Stich (1983), is both a bold, promising program for cognitive science and an alternative to naturalistic psychology (Putnam 1975). Whereas naturalistic psychology depends on the general scientific framework to fix the meanings of general terms and, hence, the content of thoughts utilizing or expressed in those terms, computational cognitive theory banishes semantical considerations in psyc…Read more
  •  20
    Coincidental Cognitive Content
    Critica 15 (45): 75-103. 1983.
  •  75
    Sensuous content
    Philosophical Papers 15 (November): 131-54. 1986.
    No abstract
  •  28
    On what might be
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 18 (3): 313-322. 1980.
  •  61
    About being a bat
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 63 (1): 26-49. 1985.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  18
    On What Might Be
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 18 (3): 313-322. 1980.
  •  23
    A New Way up from Empirical Foundations
    Synthese 49 (3). 1981.
  •  36
    The Mundane Matter of the Mental Language
    Cambridge University Press. 1989.
    Christopher Maloney offers an explanation of the fundamental nature of thought. He posits the idea that thinking involves the processing of mental representations that take the form of sentences in a covert language encoded in the mind. The theory relies upon traditional categories of psychology, including such notions as belief and desire. It also draws upon and thus inherits some of the problems of artificial intelligence which it attempts to answer, including what bestows meaning or content u…Read more
  •  41
    It's hard to believe
    Mind and Language 5 (2): 122-48. 1990.
  •  89
    Saving psychological solipsism
    Philosophical Studies 61 (March): 267-83. 1991.
  •  27
    Mental images and cognitive theory
    American Philosophical Quarterly 21 (3): 237-47. 1984.
  •  103
    Mental misrepresentation
    Philosophy of Science 57 (September): 445-58. 1990.
    An account of the contents of the propositional attitudes is fundamental to the success of the cognitive sciences if, as seems correct, the cognitive sciences do presuppose propositional attitudes. Fodor has recently pointed the way towards a naturalistic explication of mental content in his Psychosemantics (1987). Fodor's theory is a version of the causal theory of meaning and thus inherits many of its virtues, including its intrinsic plausibility. Nevertheless, the proposal may suffer from two…Read more
  • In praise of narrow minds
    In James H. Fetzer (ed.), Aspects of AI, D. 1988.
  •  100
    Sensation and scientific realism
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 46 (3): 471-482. 1986.
  • Psychology without Content (review)
    Behavior and Philosophy 14 (2): 159. 1986.
  •  98
    Content: Covariation, control, and contingency
    Synthese 100 (2): 241-90. 1994.
    The Representational Theory of the Mind allows for psychological explanations couched in terms of the contents of propositional attitudes. Propositional attitudes themselves are taken to be relations to mental representations. These representations (partially) determine the contents of the attitudes in which they figure. Thus, Representationalism owes an explanation of the contents of mental representations. This essay constitutes an atomistic theory of the content of formally or syntactically s…Read more
  •  31
    A New Model for Metaphor
    Dialectica 37 (4): 285-301. 1983.
    Metaphors are expressions in artificial, contrived, alien languages, and we understand metaphors by constructing translation schemes linking our natural, literal languages to these theoretically contrived metaphorical languages. The relation between a literal natural language and a metaphorical contrived language is like the relationship between a natively known language and a system of subsequently acquired languages etymologically emerging from that basic natural language. This model for under…Read more
  •  44
    Esse in the Metaphysics of Thomas Aquinas
    New Scholasticism 55 (2): 159-177. 1981.