•  967
    Meta‐ethics and the problem of creeping minimalism
    Philosophical Perspectives 18 (1). 2004.
    This is a paper about the problem of realism in meta-ethics (and, I hope, also in other areas, but that hope is so far pretty speculative). But it is not about the problem of whether realism is true. It is about the problem of what realism is. More specifically, it is about the question of what divides meta-ethical realists from irrealists. I start with a potted history of the Good Old Days.
  •  609
    Relativism (and expressivism) and the problem of disagreement
    Philosophical Perspectives 23 (1): 79-110. 2009.
    Many philosophers, in different areas, are tempted by what variously goes under the name of Contextualism, Speaker Relativism, Indexical Relativism. (I’ll just use Indexical Relativism in this paper.) Thinking of certain problematic expressions as deriving their content from elements of the context of use solves some problems. But it faces some problems of its own, and in this paper I’m interested in one in particular, namely, the problem of disagreement. Two alternative theories, tempting for j…Read more
  •  591
    Internalism and speaker relativism
    Ethics 101 (1): 6-26. 1990.
    In this article I set out a reason for believing in a form of metaethical relativism. In rough terms, the reason is this: a widely held thesis, internalism, tells us that to accept (sincerely assert, believe, etc.) a moral judgment logically requires having a motivating reason. Since the connection is logical, or conceptual, it must be explained by a theory of what it is to accept a moral claim. I argue that the internalist feature of moral expressions can best be explained by my version of mora…Read more
  •  489
    Dispositions and fetishes: Externalist models of moral motivation
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 61 (3): 619-638. 2000.
    Internalism says that if an agent judges that it is right for her to φ, then she is motivated to φ. The disagreement between Internalists and Externalists runs deep, and it lingers even in the face of clever intuition pumps. An argument in Michael Smith’s The Moral Problem seeks some leverage against Externalism from a point within normative theory. Smith argues by dilemma: Externalists either fail to explain why motivation tracks moral judgment in a good moral agent or they attribute a kind of …Read more
  •  439
    The supervenience argument against moral realism
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 30 (3): 13-38. 1992.
    In 1971, Simon Blackburn worked out an argument against moral realism appealing to the supervenience of the moral realm on the natural realm.1 He has since revised the argument, in part to take account of objections,2 but the basic structure remains intact. While commentators3 seem to agree that the argument is not successful, they have not agreed upon what goes wrong. I believe this is because no attempt has been made to see what happens when Blackburn's argument is addressed to particular vari…Read more
  •  414
    Structures of Normative Theories
    The Monist 76 (1): 22-40. 1993.
    Normative theorists like to divide normative theories into classes. One special point of focus has been to place utilitarianism into a larger class of theories which do not necessarily share its view about what is alone of impersonal intrinsic value, namely, individual human well-being, but do share another structural feature, roughly its demand that each person seek to maximize the realization of what is of impersonal intrinsic value. The larger class is distinguished from its complement in two…Read more
  •  405
    Practical conditionals
    In David Sobel & Steven Wall (eds.), Reasons for Action, Cambridge University Press. pp. 116--133. 2009.
  •  369
    Transforming expressivism
    Noûs 33 (4): 558-572. 1999.
    In chapter five of Wise Choices, Apt Feelings Allan Gibbard develops what he calls a ‘normative logic’ intended to solve some problems that face an expressivist theory of norms like his. The first is “the problem of embedding: The analysis applies to simple contexts, in which it is simply asserted or denied that such-and-such is rational. It says nothing about more complex normative assertions.”1 That is the problem with which I will be concerned. Though he doesn’t list it as one of the problems…Read more
  •  341
    Expressivist embeddings and minimalist truth
    Philosophical Studies 83 (1): 29-51. 1996.
    This paper is about Truth Minimalism, Norm Expressivism, and the relation between them. In particular, it is about whether Truth Minimalism can help to solve a problem thought to plague Norm Expressivism. To start with, let me explain what I mean by 'Truth Minimalism' and 'Norm Expressivism.'
  •  340
    Humean Doubts about the Practical Justification of Morality
    In Garrett Cullity & Berys Gaut (eds.), Ethics and Practical Reason, Clarendon Press. pp. 81-100. 1997.
  •  233
    In general, the technical apparatus of decision theory is well developed. It has loads of theorems, and they can be proved from axioms. Many of the theorems are interesting, and useful both from a philosophical and a practical perspective. But decision theory does not have a well agreed upon interpretation. Its technical terms, in particular, ‘utility’ and ‘preference’ do not have a single clear and uncontroversial meaning. How to interpret these terms depends, of course, on what purposes in pur…Read more
  •  229
    Quasi-Realism and the Problem of Unexplained Coincidence
    Analytic Philosophy 53 (3): 269-287. 2012.
  •  214
    Is there a supervenience problem for robust moral realism?
    Philosophical Studies 176 (6): 1391-1408. 2019.
    The paper describes the problem for robust moral realism of explaining the supervenience of the moral on the non-moral, and examines five objections to the argument: The moral does not supervene on the descriptive, because we may owe different obligations to duplicates. If the supervenience thesis is repaired to block, it becomes trivial and easy to explain. Supervenience is a moral doctrine and should get an explanation from within normative ethics rather than metaethics. Supervenience is a con…Read more
  •  206
    Metaethics and Normative Commitment
    Philosophical Issues 12 (1): 241-263. 2002.
  •  160
    The real and the quasi-real: problems of distinction
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 48 (3-4): 532-547. 2018.
    This paper surveys some ways of distinguishing Quasi-Realism in metaethics from Non-naturalist Realism, including ‘Explanationist’ methods of distinguishing, which characterize the Real by its explanatory role, and Inferentialist methods. Rather than seeking the One True Distinction, the paper adopts an irenic and pragmatist perspective, allowing that different ways of drawing the line are best for different purposes.
  •  150
    Lockean and logical truth conditions
    Analysis 64 (1): 84-91. 2004.
    1. In ‘A problem for expressivism’ Frank Jackson and Philip Pettit argue ‘that expressivists do not have a persuasive story to tell about how ethical sentences can express attitudes without reporting them and, in particular, without being true or false’ (1998: 240). Briefly: expressivists say that ethical sentences serve to express non-cognitive attitudes, but that these sentences do not report non-cognitive attitudes. The view that ethical sentences do report non-cognitive attitudes is not Expre…Read more
  •  126
    The expressivist circle: Invoking norms in the explanation of normative judgment (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65 (1). 2002.
    To naturalize normative judgment is to give some account of it, in naturalistic and non-normative terms. Simon Blackburn’s Ruling Passions embraces naturalism, about ethics especially.
  •  118
    Contemporary Debates in Moral Theory (edited book)
    Wiley-Blackwell. 2006.
    _Contemporary Debates in Moral Theory _features pairs of newly commissioned essays by some of the leading theorists working in the field today. Brings together fresh debates on the most controversial issues in moral theory Questions include: Are moral requirements derived from reason? How demanding is morality? Are virtues the proper starting point for moral theorizing? Lively debate format sharply defines the issues, and paves the way for further discussion. Will serve as an accessible introduc…Read more
  •  113
    Decision Theory and Morality
    In Piers Rawling & Al Mele (eds.), Oxford Handbook of Rationality, Oxford University Press. pp. 156--181. 2004.
    Dreier shows how the formal apparatus of decision theory is connected to some abstract issues in moral theory. He begins by explaining how to think about utility and the advice that decision theory gives us, in particular, decision theory does not assume or insist that all rational agents act in their own self-interest. Next he examines decision theory’s contributions to social contract theory, with emphasis on David Gauthier’s rationalist contractualism. Dreier’s third section considers a reint…Read more
  •  97
    Non-cognitivists claim to be able to represent normative judgment, and especially moral judgment, as an expression of a non-cognitive attitude. There is some reason to worry whether their treatment can incorporate agent centred theories, including much of common sense morality. In this paper I investigate the prospects for a non-cognitivist explanation of what is going on when we subscribe to agent centred theories or norms. The first section frames the issue by focusing on a particularly simple…Read more
  •  90
    Disagreeing (about) What to Do: Negation and Completeness in Gibbard’s Norm-Expressivism (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 72 (3). 2006.
    Brown University.
  •  83
    Gibbard and Moore
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 41 (S1): 158-164. 2003.