•  174
    Semantics of Knowledge “a positio”
    with J. K. Swindler
    Etica E Politica 11 (1): 427-437. 2009.
    This paper challenges the standard a priori/a posteriori distinction by looking at statements in which comprehension requires more that merely passive awareness of objects and their properties. A proposal is made to add to the traditional categories of knowledge, the “a positio,” characterized by active, intentional, and collective involvement of language users in the existence and nature of objects of reference needed for the truth of statements about various kinds of artifacts, broadly constru…Read more
  •  80
    Social intentions: Aggregate, collective, and general
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 26 (1): 61-76. 1996.
    The literature on collective action largely ignores the constraints that moral principle places on action-prompting intentions. Here I suggest that neither individualism nor holism can account for the generality of intentional contents demanded by universalizability principles, respect for persons, or proactive altruism. Utilitarian and communitarian ethics are criticized for nominalism with respect to social intentions. The failure of individualism and holism as grounds for moral theory is conf…Read more
  •  75
    In The Ant Trap, Brian Epstein proposes a bold new systematic strategy for developing social ontology. He explores the history and current state of the art and provides pointed critiques of leading theories in the field. His framework, incompassing frames that provide principles for grounding social facts, is developed in some detail across a variety of social practices and applied to revealing real world as well as hyporthetical examples. If Epstein's account holds, it should provide new direct…Read more
  •  54
    IN THE beginning Parmenides sought to deny the void. But he found himself trapped by his language and his thought into admitting what he sought to deny. Wisely, he counseled others to avoid the whole region in which the problem arises, lest they too be unwarily ensnared. Plato, being less easily intimidated and grasping for the first time the urgency of the paradox, unearthed each snare in turn until he felt he had found a safe path through the forbidden terrain in a new conception of being and …Read more
  •  48
    The Permanent Heartland of Subjectivity
    Idealistic Studies 25 (3): 221-229. 1995.
    One aim of that type of transcendental argument known to us as the cogito is to reveal a self about which there can be no contention, neither about its existence nor its nature. Serious doubts are, of course, perennial over whether there is any such thing as the self, if that is meant to imply that all selves have some essence or structure in common, and whether selves are best understood in terms of their intrinsic nature or external influences. Here is a dialectic that tosses us to and fro bet…Read more
  •  45
    Constructivist Moral Realism
    Southwest Philosophy Review 14 (1): 1-24. 1998.
  •  44
    Piper on Respect for Personal Autonomy and Prudential Value
    Southwest Philosophy Review 25 (2): 63-67. 2009.
  •  41
  •  36
    The Formal Distinction
    Southwest Philosophy Review 4 (1): 71-77. 1988.
  •  33
    Kenehan on Rawls on Climate Change
    Southwest Philosophy Review 23 (2): 9-12. 2007.
  •  32
    The Problem of Universals (review)
    Teaching Philosophy 17 (3): 279-281. 1994.
  •  30
    Ontology and the Practical Arena (review)
    Southwest Philosophy Review 6 (2): 125-130. 1990.
  •  28
    Falling in Love with Wisdom (review)
    Southwest Philosophy Review 9 (2): 148-150. 1993.
  •  28
    Davidson’s razor
    Southwest Philosophy Review 7 (2): 87-99. 1991.
  •  27
    Autonomy and Accountability
    Southwest Philosophy Review 26 (1): 215-223. 2010.
  •  26
    Knowledgeable Belief
    Southwest Philosophy Review 18 (1): 89-94. 2002.
  •  26
  •  25
    Butchvarov on existence
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 19 (2): 229-236. 1981.
  •  21
    Induction, Probability and Skepticism (review)
    Review of Metaphysics 46 (2): 394-396. 1992.
    Pyrrho of Elis followed Alexander into the Indus Valley where he contracted the skepticism which has ever since goaded Western thought. In this masterful study of the limits of human knowledge, D. P. Chattopadhyaya, one of India's brightest philosophical lights, revitalizes the westward flow of skepticism by putting our major epistemologies and philosophies of science to the test of his "anthropological rationalism". Often echoing Western pragmatists as well as Indians like Nägärjuna and Samkara…Read more
  •  18
    Riker on Rawls' Theory of Legitimacy
    Southwest Philosophy Review 22 (2): 123-126. 2006.
  •  18
    Simplicity: A Meta-Metaphysics by Craig Dilworth (review)
    Review of Metaphysics 68 (3): 649-651. 2015.
  •  16
    Material Identity and Sameness
    Philosophical Topics 13 (2): 69-76. 1985.
  •  16
    Material Identity and Sameness
    Philosophical Topics 13 (2): 69-76. 1985.
  •  13
    Butchvarov on Existence
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 19 (2): 229-236. 1981.
  •  11
    Weaving: An Analysis of the Constitution of Objects
    Rowman & Littlefield Publishers. 1991.
    In this moderate realist account of the whole range of issues facing contemporary analytic philosophy, J. K. Swindler aims to fill the gap in the literature between extreme realism and extreme nominalism. He discusses such fundamental concepts as existence, property, universality, individual, and necessity; analyzes the paradoxes of negative existentials and the substitutivity of co-referential terms; and defends objectivity in philosophy. The study moves through three phases: first, an argument…Read more
  •  8
    Davidson’s razor
    Southwest Philosophy Review 7 (2): 87-99. 1991.
  •  5
    Fathering for Freedom
    In Fritz Allhoff, Lon S. Nease & Michael W. Austin (eds.), Fatherhood ‐ Philosophy for Everyone, Wiley‐blackwell. 2010-09-24.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Why a Philosophy of Fatherhood? Role Responsibilities Autonomy Autonomy and Fatherhood Conclusion Notes.