Jason Adam Wasserman

Oakland University William Beaumont School of Medicine
  • Oakland University William Beaumont School of Medicine
    Associate Professor
University of Alabama, Birmingham
Sociology
PhD, 2007
CV
MI, United States of America
  •  13
    Conscientious Objection to Aggressive Interventions for Patients in a Vegetative State
    with Abram L. Brummett, Mark Christopher Navin, and Daniel Londyn Menkes
    American Journal of Bioethics 1-12. forthcoming.
    Some physicians refuse to perform life-sustaining interventions, such as tracheostomy, on patients who are very likely to remain permanently unconscious. To explain their refusal, these clinicians often invoke the language of “futility”, but this can be inaccurate and can mask problematic forms of clinical power. This paper explores whether such refusals should instead be framed as conscientious objections. We contend that the refusal to provide interventions for patients very likely to remain p…Read more
  •  10
    This article reports results of a survey about employment and compensation models for clinical ethics consultants working in the United States and discusses the relevance of these results for the professionalization of clinical ethics. This project uses self-reported data from healthcare ethics consultants to estimate compensation across different employment models. The average full-time annualized salary of respondents with a clinical doctorate is $188,310.08 (SD=$88,556.67), $146,134.85 (SD=$5…Read more
  •  6
    Moral Reasoning among HEC Members: An Empirical Evaluation of the Relationship of Theory and Practice in Clinical Ethics Consultation
    with Ernest F. Krug, Cassandra Claxton, and Shannon Lindsey Stevenson
    Journal of Clinical Ethics 26 (2): 108-117. 2015.
    In light of the ongoing development and implementation of core competencies in bioethics, it is important to proceed with a clear sense of how bioethics knowledge is utilized in the functioning of hospital ethics committees (HECs). Without such an understanding, we risk building a costly edifice on a foundation that is ambiguous at best. This article examines the empirical relationship between traditional paradigms of bioethics theory and actual decision making by HEC members using survey data f…Read more
  •  3
    Response to Stephens and Heitman
    Journal of Clinical Ethics 26 (3): 270-272. 2015.
  •  13
    Capacities to Refuse Treatment: A Reply
    American Journal of Bioethics 24 (3): 15-19. 2023.
    The three of us work as academics and clinical ethicists. In our clinical ethics work, we often encounter patients who lack decision-making capacity, but who nonetheless have strong preferences abo...
  • The social psychology of amateur ethicists: blood product recall notification and the value of reflexivity
    with L. S. Dure Iv
    Journal of Medical Ethics 34 (7): 530-533. 2008.
    The purpose of this article is to highlight ways in which institutional policymakers tend to insufficiently conceptualise their role as ethics practitioners. We use the case of blood product recall notification as a means of raising questions about the way in which, as we have observed it, discourse for those who make institutional ethics policies is constrained by routine balancing of simplified principles to the exclusion of reflexive practices—those that turn ethics reasoning back on itself. …Read more
  •  16
    The purpose of this article is to highlight ways in which institutional policymakers tend to insufficiently conceptualise their role as ethics practitioners. We use the case of blood product recall notification as a means of raising questions about the way in which, as we have observed it, discourse for those who make institutional ethics policies is constrained by routine balancing of simplified principles to the exclusion of reflexive practices—those that turn ethics reasoning back on itself. …Read more
  •  9
    In this commentary, I explore the usefulness of the framework Abram Brummett and Erica K. Salter present in their article “Mapping the Moral Terrain of Clinical Deception.” Deception cases are divisive because they nearly always evoke the metadilemma of clinical ethics: a clash between duties (in these cases, truth telling) and consequences (whatever good might come of the lie). Here, I describe a patient case in which the clinical team considered deceiving a patient about his pain‐medicine dosa…Read more
  •  33
    According to a standard account of patient decision-making capacity, patients can provide ethically valid consent or refusal only if they are able to understand and appreciate their medical c...
  •  14
    There is a perpetrator historiography of the Holocaust and a Jewish historiography of the Holocaust. The former has received the lion’s share of attention in bioethics, particularly in the form of warnings about medicine’s potential for complicity in human atrocity. However, stories of Jewish physicians during the Holocaust are instructive for positive bioethics, one that moves beyond warnings about what not to do. In exercising both explicit and introspective forms of resistance, the heroic wor…Read more
  •  37
    The capacity to designate a surrogate is not simply another kind of medical decision-making capacity. A patient with DMC can express a preference, understand information relevant to that choice, appreciate the significance of that information for their clinical condition, and reason about their choice in light of their goals and values. In contrast, a patient can possess the CDS even if they cannot appreciate their condition or reason about the relative risks and benefits of their options. Patie…Read more
  •  361
    Reasons to Accept Vaccine Refusers in Primary Care
    with Mark Christopher Navin and Douglas Opel
    Pediatrics 146 (6). 2020.
    Vaccine refusal forces us to confront tensions between many values, including scientific expertise, parental rights, children’s best interests, social responsibility, public trust, and community health. Recent outbreaks of vaccine-preventable and emerging infectious diseases have amplified these issues. The prospect of a coronavirus disease 2019 vaccine signals even more friction on the horizon. In this contentious sociopolitical landscape, it is therefore more important than ever for clinicians…Read more
  •  33
    Rasing the ivory tower: the production of knowledge and distrust of medicine among African Americans
    with M. A. Flannery and J. M. Clair
    Journal of Medical Ethics 33 (3): 177-180. 2007.
    African American distrust of medicine has consequences for treatment seeking and healthcare behaviour. Much work has been done to examine acute events that have contributed to this phenomenon and a sophisticated bioethics discipline keeps watch on current practices by medicine. But physicians and clinicians are not the only actors in the medical arena, particularly when it comes to health beliefs and distrust of medicine. The purpose of this paper is to call attention not just to ethical shortco…Read more
  •  719
    Problematics of Grounded Theory: Innovations for Developing an Increasingly Rigorous Qualitative Method
    with Jeffrey Michael Clair and Kenneth L. Wilson
    Qualitative Research 9 (3): 355-381. 2009.
    Our purpose in this article is to identify and suggest resolution for two core problematics of grounded theory. First, while grounded theory provides transparency to one part of the conceptualization process, where codes emerge directly from the data, it provides no such systematic or transparent way for gaining insight into the conceptual relationships between discovered codes. Producing a grounded theory depends not only on the definition of conceptual pieces, but the delineation of a relation…Read more
  •  38
    Two new documents from the Committee on Bioethics of the American Academy of Pediatrics expand the terrain for parental decision making, suggesting that pediatricians may override only those parental requests that cross a harm threshold. These new documents introduce a broader set of considerations in favor of parental authority in pediatric care than previous AAP documents have embraced. While we find this to be a positive move, we argue that the 2016 AAP positions actually understate the impor…Read more
  •  34
    Children’s preferences about medical treatment—like the preferences of other patients—hold moral weight in decision-making that is independent of considerations of autonomy or best interests. In light of this understanding of the moral value of patient preferences, the American Academy of Pediatrics could strengthen the ethical foundation for its formal guidance on pediatric assent.
  •  17
    Pediatric Assent and Treating Children Over Objection
    with Mark Christopher Navin and John Vercler
    Pediatrics 144 (5). 2019.
    More than 20 years ago, the pioneering pediatric ethicist William Bartholome wrote a fiery letter to the editor of this journal because he thought a recently published statement on pediatric assent, from the Committee on Bioethics of the American Academy of Pediatrics (AAP), showed insufficient respect for children. That AAP statement, like its 2016 update, asserts that pediatric assent should be solicited only when a child’s dissent will be honored. Bartholome objected that pediatricians…Read more
  •  9
    Ships that should pass in the night
    Philosophy Now 48 25-28. 2004.
  •  38
    When Respecting Autonomy Is Harmful: A Clinically Useful Approach to the Nocebo Effect
    with Daniel Londyn Menkes and John T. Fortunato
    American Journal of Bioethics 17 (6): 36-42. 2017.
    Nocebo effects occur when an adverse effect on the patient arises from the patient's own negative expectations. In accordance with informed consent, providers often disclose information that results in unintended adverse outcomes for the patient. While this may adhere to the principle of autonomy, it violates the doctrine of “primum non nocere,” given that side-effect disclosure may cause those side effects. In this article we build off previous work, particularly by Wells and Kaptchuk and by Co…Read more
  •  34
    Two core questions in pediatric ethics concern when and how physicians are ethically permitted to intervene in parental treatment decisions (intervention principles), and the goals or values that should direct physicians’ and parents’ decisions about the care of children (guidance principles). Lainie Friedman Ross argues in this issue of The Journal of Clinical Ethics that constrained parental autonomy (CPA) simultaneously answers both questions: physicians should intervene when parental treatm…Read more
  •  28
    The field of clinical bioethics strongly advocates for the use of advance directives to promote patient autonomy, particularly at the end of life. This paper reports a study of clinical bioethicists’ perceptions of the professional consensus about advance directives, as well as their personal advance care planning practices. We find that clinical bioethicists are often sceptical about the value of advance directives, and their personal choices about advance directives often deviate from what cli…Read more
  •  30
    When a patient lacks decision-making capacity, then according to standard clinical ethics practice in the United States, the health care team should seek guidance from a surrogate decision-maker, either previously selected by the patient or appointed by the courts. If there are no surrogates willing or able to exercise substituted judgment, then the team is to choose interventions that promote a patient’s best interests. We argue that, even when there is input from a surrogate, patient preferenc…Read more
  •  10
    Nonmaleficence, Nondisclosure, and Nocebo: Response to Open Peer Commentaries
    with John T. Fortunato and Daniel Londyn Menkes
    American Journal of Bioethics 17 (7): 4-5. 2017.
  •  22
  •  49
    Experimental evidence showing that physician guidance promotes perceptions of physician empathy
    with Daniel Russell Hans and Priyanka Dubé
    AJOB Empirical Bioethics 7 (3): 135-139. 2016.
  •  42
    We agree with Emily Walsh (2020) that the current preferences of patients with dementia should sometimes supersede those patients’ advance directives. We also agree that consensus clinical ethics guidance does a poor job of explaining the moral value of such patients’ preferences. Furthermore, Walsh correctly notes that clinicians are often averse to treating patients with dementia over their objections, and that this aversion reflects clinical wisdom that can inform revisions to clinical ethics…Read more
  •  21
    Calls for incorporating social science into patient care typically have accounted for neither the logistic constraints of medical training nor the methodological fallacies of utilizing aggregate “social facts” in clinical practice. By elucidating the different epistemic approaches of artistic and scientific practices, this paper illustrates an integrative artistic pedagogy that allows clinical practitioners to generate social scientific insights from actual patient encounters. Although there is …Read more
  •  17
    Placebo Analgesia as Nocebo Reduction
    with John T. Fortunato and Daniel Londyn Menkes
    American Journal of Bioethics Neuroscience 9 (3): 198-199. 2018.
  •  8
    When Do Pediatricians Call the Ethics Consultation Service? Impact of Clinical Experience and Formal Ethics Training
    with Mark C. Navin, Susanna Jain, Katie R. Baughman, and Naomi T. Laventhal
    AJOB Empirical Bioethics 11 (2): 83-90. 2020.
    Background: Previous research shows that pediatricians inconsistently utilize the ethics consultation service (ECS). Methods: Pediatricians in two suburban, Midwestern academic hospitals were asked to reflect on their ethics training and utilization of ECS via an anonymous, electronic survey distributed in 2017 and 2018, and analyzed in 2018. Participants reported their clinical experience, exposure to formal and informal ethics training, use of formal and informal ethics consultations, and pote…Read more