• Brock University
    Department of Philosophy
    Other faculty (Postdoc, Visiting, etc)
St. Catharines, Ontario, Canada
  •  172
    The problem of evil and the attributes of God
    International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 26 (3). 1989.
    In discussions of the probabilistic argument from evil, some defenders of theism have recently argued that evil has no evidential force against theism. They base their argument on the claim that there is no reason to think that we should be able to discern morally sufficient reasons which God presumably has for permitting the evil which occurs. In this paper I try to counter this argument by discussing factors which suggest that we should generally be able to discern why God permits evil events.…Read more
  •  132
    A Moral Argument Against Miracles
    Faith and Philosophy 12 (1): 54-78. 1995.
    Those who believe that miracles (temporary suspensions of some law of nature accomplished by divine power) have occurred typically hold that they are rare and that only a small percentage of all people have been eyewitnesses to them or been direct beneficiaries of them. Although a claim that they occur far more frequently would be empirically highly implausible, I argue that the claim that God performs miracles in such a pattern unavoidably implies that God is guilty of unfairness. I articulate …Read more
  •  94
    In Foundationalism, Coherentism, and the Levels Gambit, David Shatz argued that foundationalists must countenance a circular mediate justification of perceptual beliefs which the foundationalist holds are already immediately justified. Because the circularity of coherentist accounts of the justification of beliefs is a major basis of foundationalist criticism of coherentism, Shatz's claim is a serious challenge to foundationalism. In this paper, using a moderate foundationalism with a reliabilis…Read more
  •  91
    The hiddenness of God and the problem of evil
    International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 37 (1). 1995.
  •  84
    Christianity and Consequentialism
    Faith and Philosophy 6 (2): 198-206. 1989.
    In a recent paper, Gilbert Meilaender argues that Christian ethics must not be consequentialist. Though Meilaender does indicate some problems which may exist with certain consequentialist theories, those problems do not exclude all types of consequentialist theories from consideration as Christian ethical theories. A consequentialism like R. M. Hare’s offers virtually all the advantages Meilaender claims for his Christian deontological view. Moreover. Meilaender has overlooked certain advantage…Read more
  •  53
    Comtemporary Christian Doubts About the Resurrection
    Faith and Philosophy 5 (1): 40-60. 1988.
    In a recent issue of Faith and Philosophy, Stephen Davis argues that it is rational for supernaturalists, though not for naturalists, to believe in the resurrection of Jesus Christ in (roughly) the sense of an event which happened to Jesus in which Jesus, though he had truly died, was restored to life and consciousness and after which his living body left the tomb. After making some clarifications regarding supernaturalism and the concept of a miracle, I argue that Davis has not shown this. My c…Read more
  •  51
    Comtemporary Christian Doubts About the Resurrection
    Faith and Philosophy 5 (1): 40-60. 1988.
    In a recent issue of Faith and Philosophy, Stephen Davis argues that it is rational for supernaturalists, though not for naturalists, to believe in the resurrection of Jesus Christ in (roughly) the sense of an event which happened to Jesus in which Jesus, though he had truly died, was restored to life and consciousness and after which his living body left the tomb. After making some clarifications regarding supernaturalism and the concept of a miracle, I argue that Davis has not shown this. My c…Read more
  •  39
    Books received (review)
    International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 62 (1): 199-202. 2007.
  •  36
    Reflections on a Methodology for Christian Philosophers
    Faith and Philosophy 5 (2): 144-158. 1988.
    In a recent article in FAITH AND PHILOSOPHY, Alvin Plantinga advised Christian philosophers to philosophize in light of their fundamental beliefs as Christians. Believing that his discussion does not give proper weight to the necessary role of secular beliefs in modifying our Christian beliefs, in this article I propose that Christian beliefs and secular beliefs should be related more dialectically than Plantinga suggests--i.e., that neither should always be given precedence. I defend this propo…Read more
  •  36
    Atheism (review)
    Faith and Philosophy 10 (1): 112-119. 1993.
  •  34
    Accepting the Authority of the Bible
    Faith and Philosophy 6 (4): 378-397. 1989.
    This paper provides an answer to this question: is the Christian of today rationally justified in using the views expressed in the Bible as a (or the) standard for what she should accept for her own beliefs and practices. I argue against trying to answer this question on thebasis of some alleged character of the biblical writings (e.g., their inerrancy or inspiredness). Such a thesis would itself have to be rationally justified, as would the interpretations and applications of biblical writings …Read more
  •  33
    God, Action, and Embodiment (review)
    Faith and Philosophy 2 (1): 83-86. 1985.
  •  33
    Should Christian Theologians Become Christian Philosophers?
    Faith and Philosophy 12 (2): 260-268. 1995.
    This paper continues a debate about the relation between Christian philosophers and theologians begun by Gordon Kaufman, who argued that Christian theologians need not be interested in “evidentialism.” In particular it replies to a paper by William Hasker charging that an earlier defense of Kaufman’s position introduced tensions because it required judgments about the merits of “evidentialism” which could be defended only by using the evidentialist arguments whose importance Kaufman denied. This…Read more
  •  33
    Epistemology (review)
    Faith and Philosophy 1 (3): 339-343. 1984.
  •  20
    Response to Davis
    Faith and Philosophy 7 (1): 112-116. 1990.
  •  19
    Divine Power in Process Theism (review)
    Process Studies 17 (3): 200-205. 1988.
  •  18
    Reported Miracles (review)
    Faith and Philosophy 13 (2): 286-293. 1996.
  •  17
    Christianity and Philosophy (review)
    Faith and Philosophy 5 (1): 91-93. 1988.
  •  16
  •  13
    Reported Miracles (review)
    Faith and Philosophy 13 (2): 286-293. 1996.
  •  11
    Epistemology (review)
    Faith and Philosophy 1 (3): 339-343. 1984.
  •  11
    Atheism (review)
    Faith and Philosophy 10 (1): 112-119. 1993.
  •  10
    Why do bad things happen, even to good people? If there is a God, why aren't God's existence and God's will for humans more apparent? And if God really does miracles for some people, why not for others? This book examines these three problems of evil - suffering, divine hiddenness, and unfairness if miracles happen as believers claim - to explore how different ideas of God's power relate to the problem of evil.
  •  7
    Process Theism and Theodicies for Problems of Evil
    In Justin P. McBrayer & Daniel Howard‐Snyder (eds.), The Blackwell Companion to the Problem of Evil, Wiley. 2013.
    I delineate four problems of evil encountered by Christian traditional theists (those who believe that God is all good, all knowing, and all powerful), and I present reasons for thinking that they have no good responses to these problems. Then I delineate important features of process metaphysics and discuss how this metaphysics solves the problems of evil. As conceived by process theists, God is all‐good and all‐knowing and has the greatest power any one being could have, but is not all‐powerfu…Read more
  •  5
    Books Received (review)
    International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 65 (3): 183-185. 2009.
  •  3
    Books received (review)
    International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 67 (3): 193-195. 2010.