•  8
    Rigidita predikátů
    Pro-Fil 11 (2): 13-26. 2011.
    Zatímco v případě otázek rigidity singulárních termínů panuje obecná shoda, v případě rigidity predikátů tomu tak překvapivě není. Záměrem této statě je opřít distinkci rigidní / nerigidní o jasné pojmy, jmenovitě o pojem reference v určité sémantické teorii. V důsledku toho lze podat rigorózní definici pojmu rigidního designátoru individua. Tato definice je pak přímočaře adaptovatelná pro případ pojmu rigidního designátoru třídy individuí (apod.). Tímto je dosaženo nejen obecnosti, ale i vnitřn…Read more
  •  5
    Je paradox holiče paradoxem?
    Pro-Fil 12 (2): 3. 2012.
    V první části textu ukazuji, že paradox holiče není analogický Russellově paradoxu, ba že to vůbec není paradox. Poté se stručně věnuji otázce jeho pravděpodobného historického původu i původu jeho známých verzí. V závěru diskutuji zdroj jeho údajné paradoxnosti.
  •  6
    Pravda a paradox: úvod do problematiky
    Pro-Fil 10 (2): 13-22. 2010.
    Tato stať je zamýšlena jako úvod do spojité problematiky explikace pravdivosti a sémantic-kých paradoxů, které onu explikaci pronásledují. Tyto paradoxy jsou viděny jako prostředek ukázání, že nedostatečně promyšlená explikace našeho pojmu pravdivosti (významu pravdi-vostního predikátu) je explikací nevyhovující. Poté jsou předvedeny rysy obou klasických přístupů, Russellovy teorie typů a Tarského hierarchie metajazyků. Nakonec jsou podány zá-kladní ideje hlavních názorových škol, které přišly p…Read more
  • On the Czech Logic in the 20th Century
    In Andrew Schumann (ed.), Logic in Central and Eastern Europe, Rowman & Littlefield. pp. 229-243. 2012.
    On the first part, a historical overview of the development of the Czech logic from 1900 until nowadays is sketched. In the second part, theyare listed Czech logicians, mentioning their key topics and books.
  •  17
    On Partiality and Tichý's Transparent Intensional Logic
    Magyar Filozofiai Szemle 54 (4): 120-128. 2010.
    The paper focuses on treating partiality within Tichý’s logical system. Tichý’s logic is two-valued and type-theoretic. His simple theory of types (and the deduction system for it) accepts both total and partial functions. Tichý’s late framework is explicitly ramified. So-called constructions (roughly: algorithms) construct, e.g., values of functions at arguments; in some cases, however, they do not construct anything at all. …Read more
  • Co jsou Russellovy propoziční funkce [What Russell's Propositional Functions Are]
    Filosoficky Casopis 61 (Supplementary2): 109-146. 2013.
    The aim of this study is to elucidate the notion of propositional function as exposed by Russell within the no-class theory of Principia Mathematica. According to realistic interpretation, propositional functions are metaphysical objects consisting of individuals, objectual variables and attributes. According to nominalistic interpretation, however, they are rather linguistic expressions. I argue that the latter interpretation is more adequate than the former one.
  • This paper follows in Pavel Tichý’s concept of distinguishing between trivial (i.e. constant) and non-trivial properties. This classification has been extended by Pavel Cmorej who distinguished two kinds of non-trivial properties, namely purely empirical and partly essential (which are partly empirical) properties (partly essential property is essential for certain individual(s), but that it is not for other(s)). The present study provides rigorous formal definitions…Read more
  •  14
    Abstract and Concrete Individuals and Projection
    Organon F: Medzinárodný Časopis Pre Analytickú Filozofiu 24 (supplementary): 74-88. 2017.
    Two kinds of individuals are distinguished: abstract and concrete. Whereas abstract individuals belong to our conceptual sphere, concrete individuals (i.e. particulars) individuate the world of matter. A subject investigating the external world projects abstract individuals onto concrete ones. The proposal offers a solution to various metaphysical and epistemological puzzles concerned with individuals, e.g., the Ship of Theseus, the Polish Logician, problems with reidentification, or proper name…Read more
  •  6
    Constructional vs. Denotational Conception of Aboutness
    Organon F: Medzinárodný Časopis Pre Analytickú Filozofiu 21 (2): 219-236. 2014.
    Anotace Following Carnap's Principle of Subject Matter, Pavel Tichý proposed a methodological principle I call the "Denotational Principle of Aboutness". It says that expressions are about their denotata. Denotata are modelled as possible world intensions or (common) extensions. Nearly the same principle was recently defended by Marie Duží and Pavel Materna under the name the "Parmenides Principle". However, Duží and Materna did not react to Tichý's late proposal which I call the "Constructional…Read more
  •  1
    Explicating the Notion of Truth Within Transparent Intensional Logic
    In Roberto Ciuni, Heinrich Wansing & Caroline Willkommen (eds.), Recent Trends in Philosophical Logic (Proceedings of Trends in Logic XI), Springer. pp. 167-177. 2014.
    The approach of Transparent Intensional Logic to truth differs significantly from rivalling approaches. The notion of truth is explicated by a three-level system of notions whereas the upper-level notions depend on the lower-level ones. Truth of possible world propositions lies in the bottom. Truth of hyperintensional entities – called constructions – which determine propositions is dependent on it. Truth of expressions depends on truth of their meanings; the meanings are explicated as construct…Read more
  •  21
    Russellian typing knowledge and Fitch's paradox of knowability
    In Jean-Yves Beziau, Alexandre Costa-Leite & Itala M. Loffredo D’Ottaviano (eds.), Aftermath of the Logical Paradise. pp. 401-423. 2017.
    It is already known that Fitch's paradox of knowability can be solved by typing knowledge. I differentiate two kinds of such typing, Tarskian and Russellian, and focus on the latter which is framed within the ramified theory of types. My main aim is to other a defence of the approach against recently raised criticism. The key justification is provided by the Vicious Circle Principle which governs the very formation of propositions and thus also intensional operators, including the operator of kn…Read more
  • Tichý's Possible Worlds
    Organon F: Medzinárodný Časopis Pre Analytickú Filozofiu 21 (4). 2014.
    Pavel Tichy originally published his interesting conception of possible worlds in 1968. Even though he modified it over the following twenty five years, its core remained unchanged. None of his thirty journal papers or books containing the notion of possible worlds was a study in metaphysics, Tichy (and most of his followers) always introduced the notion in the context of other investigations where he applied his Transparent intensional logic either to the semantic analysis of natural language o…Read more
  •  3
    Williamson, Linsky, Paseau and others proposed a solution to Church- Fitch's knowability paradox that is based on typing knowledge; however, it received some criticism. Carrara and Fassio objected that the approach has no paradox-independent motivation, it is thus ad hoc. In the first part of the paper, I dismiss such criticism by carefully stating typing approach principles that are based on non-circular formation of propositions and intensional operators operating on them. In the second part o…Read more
  •  79
    Projikování a abstraktní vs. konkrétní individua
    Studia Neoaristotelica 6 (2): 234-246. 2009.
    Two kinds of individuals are distinguished: abstract and concrete. Whereas abstract individuals belong to our conceptual sphere, concrete individuals (i.e. particulars) individuate the world of matter. A subject inquiring the external world projects abstract individuals onto the concrete ones (i.e. pieces of matter). Our theory offers a solution to various ontological and epistemological puzzles concerned with individuals, e.g., the Ship of Theseus, Polish Logician, problems with reidentificatio…Read more
  •  21
    The Barber paradox is often introduced as a popular version of Russell’s paradox, though some experts have denied their similarity, evencalling the Barber paradox a pseudoparadox. In the first part of thepaper, I demonstrate mainly that in the standard (Quinean) defini-tion of a paradox the Barber paradox is a clear-cut example of a non-paradox. Despite some outward similarities, it differs radically fromRussell’s paradox. I also expose many other differences. In the secondpa…Read more
  • I examine the familiar quadruple of categorical statements “Every F is/is not G.”, “Some F is/is not G.” as well as the quadruple of their modal versions “Necessarily, every F is/is not G.”, “Possibly, some F is/is not G.”. I focus on their existential import and its impact on the resulting Squares of Opposition. Though my construal of existential import follows modern approach, I add some extra details which are enabled by framing my definition of existential import within expressively rich hig…Read more
  • Two Standard and Two Modal Squares of Opposition
    In Jean-Yves Béziau & Gianfranco Basti (eds.), The Square of Opposition: A Cornerstone of Thought, Birkhäuser. pp. 119-142. 2016.
    In this study, we examine modern reading of the Square of Opposition by means of Tichý's Transparent intensional logic. Explicit use of possible world semantics helps us to sharply discriminate between standard and modal readings of categorial statements. We thus get two basic versions of the Square, whereas the Modal Square has not been fully introduced in the contemporary debate yet. Some properties ascribed by mediaeval logicians to the Square require a shift from its Standard to Modal versio…Read more
  • The problem of hyperintensional contexts, and the problem of logical omniscience, shows the severe limitation of possible-worlds semantics which is employed also in standard epistemic logic. As a solution, we deploy here hyperintensional semantics according to which the meaning of an expression is an abstract structured algorithm, namely Tichý's construction. Constructions determine the denotata of expressions. Propositional attitudes are modelled as attitudes towards constructions of truth valu…Read more
  • Protipříklady proti kauzální teorii vlastních jmen
    Filosoficky Casopis 53 669-690. 2005.
    [Counterexamples to the causal theory of proper names]
  • „Nemožné“ možné světy
    Filosoficky Casopis 48 1035-1036. 2000.
    [“Impossible“ Possible Worlds]
  • Jazyk jakožto kód a logická analýza
    Filosoficky Casopis 55 95-105. 2007.
    [Language as a code and logical analysis]
  • Jména a deskripce. : logicko-sémantická zkoumání
    Filosoficky Casopis 58 933-936. 2010.
    [Names and descriptions: A logical-semantic investigation]
  • Nietzsche bez Nietzscha?
    Filosoficky Casopis 52 480-482. 2004.
    [Nietzsche without Nietzsche?]
  • „Individua na odpočinku“: několik komentářů
    Filosoficky Casopis 50 301-310. 2002.
    [”Individuals taking a break” some comments]
  • Charakter logické analýzy přirozeného jazyka
    Filosoficky Casopis 53 925-935. 2005.
    [The character of logical analysis of natural language]
  • Co je sémantika
    Filosoficky Casopis 54 267-279. 2006.
    [Semantics, what it is]
  •  51
    The Modal Argument against Nominal Description Theory
    Kriterion - Journal of Philosophy 31 (1): 77-100. 2017.
    The paper examines Loar’s and Bach’s defence of Nominal Description Theory against Kripkean Modal Argument (MA). Using formal tools of hyperintensional logic, I discriminate three kinds of nominal description which are possible substitutes for a proper name, thus considering various readings of the MA. On its natural understanding, the MA is valid – contrary to what Loar and Bach say. On the other hand, the soundness of the MA remains doubtful, as pointed out already by Loar and Bach.