•  221
    Presupposition and entailment
    Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 17 (2): 272-278. 1976.
  •  33
    Scriven on The Logic of Cause
    Theory and Decision 6 (1): 43-55. 1975.
    In a recent article entitled, ‘The Logic of Cause’ Scriven has presented a series of formidable arguments against the possibility of explicating the concept of cause in terms of the concepts of sufficient condition and necessary condition. Some of his main arguments center on the difficulties of capturing the asymmetry of cause and effect and of handling a certain kind of over-determination he calls linked overdetermination. Scriven's contention that there is no way to capture the asymmetry of c…Read more
  •  368
    Epistemic Closure and Skepticism
    with Fred Adams
    Logos and Episteme 1 (2): 221-246. 2010.
    Closure is the epistemological thesis that if S knows that P and knows that P implies Q, then if S infers that Q, S knows that Q. Fred Dretske acknowledges that closure is plausible but contends that it should be rejected because it conflicts with the plausible thesis: Conclusive reasons (CR): S knows that P only if S believes P on the basis of conclusive reasons, i.e., reasons S wouldn‘t have if it weren‘t the case that P. Dretske develops an analysis of knowing that centers on CR, and argues t…Read more
  •  91
    Conclusive reasons, knowledge, and action
    with Fred Adams
    Philosophical Issues 22 (1): 35-52. 2012.
    The article presents information on the capabilities of Dretske-style analysis of knowing (DAK) and of several competing analyses with respect to accounting for the apparent facts. It informs that the DAK can ground plausible verdicts about knowledge and ignorance in cases involving lotteries. It further informs that the knowledge-efficacy donor imply the implausible thesis.
  • Relevance Logic and Inferential Knowledge
    In J. Norman & R. Sylvan (eds.), Directions in Relevant Logic, Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 317-326. 1989.
  •  289
    Knowledge as Fact-Tracking True Belief
    Manuscrito 40 (4): 1-30. 2017.
    ABSTRACT Drawing inspiration from Fred Dretske, L. S. Carrier, John A. Barker, and Robert Nozick, we develop a tracking analysis of knowing according to which a true belief constitutes knowledge if and only if it is based on reasons that are sensitive to the fact that makes it true, that is, reasons that wouldn’t obtain if the belief weren’t true. We show that our sensitivity analysis handles numerous Gettier-type cases and lottery problems, blocks pathways leading to skepticism, and validates t…Read more
  •  85
    Aristotle vs. Diodorus
    with Thomas D. Paxson Jr
    Philosophy Research Archives 11 41-76. 1985.
    We develop a modified system of standard logic, Augmented Standard Logic (ASL), and we employ ASL in an effort to show that, contrary to prevailing opinion, both Aristotle and Diodorus presented impressive arguments, having valid structures and highly plausible premisses, in their famous fatalism debate. We argue that ASL, which contains standard logic and a full system of modal and temporal logic emanating from a modicum of primitives, should not only enable one to appreciate the sophisticated …Read more
  •  311
    Computer modeling and the fate of folk psychology
    Metaphilosophy 33 (1-2): 30-48. 2002.
    Although Paul Churchland and Jerry Fodor both subscribe to the so-called theory-theory– the theory that folk psychology (FP) is an empirical theory of behavior – they disagree strongly about FP’s fate. Churchland contends that FP is a fundamentally flawed view analogous to folk biology, and he argues that recent advances in computational neuroscience and connectionist AI point toward development of a scientifically respectable replacement theory that will give rise to a new common-sense psycholo…Read more
  •  19
    Book reviews (review)
    Philosophical Psychology 10 (2): 231-257. 1997.
    Consciousness and experience, William G. Lycan. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1996. ISBN 0–262–12197–2 (hc)Mind as motion: explorations in the dynamics of cognition, Robert Port & Timothy Van Gelder (Eds). Cambridge, MA: MIT/Bradford, 1995. ISBN 0–262–16150–8Perception, Kathleen Akins (Ed.). New York: Oxford University Press, 1996. ISBN 0–19–508461 (hbk); 0–19–508462–4 (pbk)Context and consciousness, B. Nardi (Ed.). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1996. ISBN: 0–262–14058–6Catching ourselves in the act, Ho…Read more
  •  432
    Methods Matter: Beating the Backward Clock
    Logos and Episteme 8 (1): 99-112. 2017.
    In “Beat the (Backward) Clock,” we argued that John Williams and Neil Sinhababu’s Backward Clock Case fails to be a counterexample to Robert Nozick’s or Fred Dretske’s Theories of Knowledge. Williams’ reply to our paper, “There’s Nothing to Beat a Backward Clock: A Rejoinder to Adams, Barker and Clarke,” is a further attempt to defend their counterexample against a range of objections. In this paper, we argue that, despite the number and length of footnotes, Williams is still wrong.
  •  132
    Towards closure on closure
    with Fred Adams and Julia Figurelli
    Synthese 188 (2): 179-196. 2012.
    Tracking theories of knowledge are widely known to have the consequence that knowledge is not closed. Recent arguments by Vogel and Hawthorne claim both that there are no legitimate examples of knowledge without closure and that the costs of theories that deny closure are too great. This paper considers the tracking theories of Dretske and Nozick and the arguments by Vogel and Hawthorne. We reject the arguments of Vogel and Hawthorne and evaluate the costs of closure denial for tracking theories…Read more
  •  310
    Beat the (Backward) Clock
    Logos and Episteme 7 (3): 353-361. 2016.
    In a recent very interesting and important challenge to tracking theories of knowledge, Williams & Sinhababu claim to have devised a counter-example to tracking theories of knowledge of a sort that escapes the defense of those theories by Adams & Clarke. In this paper we will explain why this is not true. Tracking theories are not undermined by the example of the backward clock, as interesting as the case is.
  •  14
    Cause and Condition
    Proceedings of the XVth World Congress of Philosophy 5 503-506. 1975.
  •  1
    A System of Intensional Logic
    Dissertation, Tulane University. 1967.
  •  26
    Socratic ignorance vindicated
    Philosophical Studies 28 (1). 1975.
  •  47
    Hypotheticals: Conditionals and theticals
    Philosophical Quarterly 23 (93): 335-345. 1973.
  •  79
  •  36
    A paradox of knowing whether
    Mind 84 (334): 281-283. 1975.
  •  64
    The Fallacy of Begging the Question
    Dialogue 15 (2): 241-255. 1976.
    Begging the question — roughly, positing in the premises what is to be proved in the conclusion — is a perplexing fallacy.1 Are not question-begging arguments valid? Yes, we may find ourselves saying, but they are fallacious despite their validity, owing to their inability to establish the truth of a conclusion which is not already known. But are not question-begging arguments sometimes effective in bringing an audience to an awareness of the truth of the conclusion? How can a dialectical maneuv…Read more
  •  38
    'If', '⊃', and the principle of exportation
    Philosophical Studies 26 (2). 1974.
  •  52
    A Note on Knowledge and Belief
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 5 (1). 1975.
  •  24
    Audi's Theory of Practical Reasoning
    Behavior and Philosophy 19 (2). 1991.
  •  28
    The Nature of Question-Begging Arguments
    Dialogue 17 (3): 490-498. 1978.
  •  84
    'If' and 'Even If'
    Analysis 40 (2). 1980.