•  31
    Why future contingents are not all false
    Analytic Philosophy. forthcoming.
    Patrick Todd argues for a modified Peircean view on which all future contingents are false. According to Todd, this is the only view that makes sense if we fully embrace an open future, rejecting the idea of actual future history. I argue that supervaluational accounts, on which future contingents are neither true nor false, are fully consistent with the metaphysics of an open future. I suggest that it is Todd's failure to distinguish semantic and postsemantic levels that leads him to suppose ot…Read more
  •  101
    Belief: What is it Good for?
    Erkenntnis 1-18. forthcoming.
    Abstract“Absolutely nothing,” say the radical Bayesians. “Simplifying decisions,” say the moderates. “Providing premises in practical reasoning,” say the epistemologists. “Coordinating with others,” say I. It is hard to see how to construct an adequate theory of rational behavior without using a graded notion of belief, such as credence. But once we have credence, what role is left for belief? After surveying some answers to this question, I will explore the idea that belief is in a different li…Read more
  •  20
    The Things We (Sorta Kinda) Believe
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 73 (1): 218-224. 2006.
  •  16
    I applaud Maria Baghramian and Annalisa Coliva (henceforth B&C) for writing this book. Like Baghramian’s earlier book of the same title (Baghramian 2004), i.
  •  16
    "Philosophical logic" describes two distinct areas: the investigation of the fundamental concepts of logic, the formal investigation of alternatives and extensions to classical logic. The first is a philosophical discipline, concerned with notions like truth, propositions, necessity, logical consequence, vagueness, and reasoning. The second is a technical discipline, devoted to developing formal logical systems-modal logics, second-order logics, intuitionistic logics, relevance logics, logics of…Read more
  •  93
    A Map of Metaphysics Zeta (review)
    Philosophical Review 112 (1): 97-99. 2003.
    The central chapter of Burnyeat’s Map is organized like a commentary, moving through Metaphysics Ζ (and parts of Η) section by section. But unlike a commentary, it does not strive for comprehensiveness. Its aim is to describe the general lay of the land—what is being argued for where, in what way, and why— and so its exegesis is limited to Aristotle’s “signposts.” For example, every time Aristotle says “we must investigate” or “as we have seen,” Burnyeat asks “where?” As far as possible, he trie…Read more
  •  111
    The things we (sorta kinda) believe (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 73 (1). 2006.
    On Schiffer’s new view, propositions are easy to come by. Any that-clause can be counted on to express one. Thus, trivially, there are vague propositions, conditional propositions, moral and aesthetic propositions. And where propositions go, truth and falsity follow: barring paradoxical cases, Schiffer accepts instances of the schemata “the proposition that p is true iff p” and “the proposition that p is false iff not-p.” What isn’t easy to find, Schiffer thinks, is determinate truth. By the end…Read more
  • The Assessment Sensitivity of Knowledge Attributions
    In Tamar Szabo Gendler & John Hawthorne (eds.), Oxford Studies in Epistemology Volume 1, Oxford University Press Uk. 2005.
  •  106
    Indeterminacy as Indecision, Lecture I: Vagueness and Communication
    Journal of Philosophy 117 (11/12): 593-616. 2020.
    I can say that a building is tall and you can understand me, even if neither of us has any clear idea exactly how tall a building must be in order to count as tall. This mundane fact poses a problem for the view that successful communication consists in the hearer’s recognition of the proposition a speaker intends to assert. The problem cannot be solved by the epistemicist’s usual appeal to anti-individualism, because the extensions of vague words like ‘tall’ are contextually fluid and can be co…Read more
  •  42
    Indeterminacy as Indecision, Lecture II: Seeing through the Clouds
    Journal of Philosophy 117 (11/12): 617-642. 2020.
    One approach to the problem is to keep the orthodox notion of a proposition but innovate in the theory of speech acts. A number of philosophers and linguists have suggested that, in cases of felicitous underspecification, a speaker asserts a “cloud” of propositions rather than just one. This picture raises a number of questions: what norms constrain a “cloudy assertion,” what counts as uptake, and how is the conversational common ground revised if it is accepted? I explore three different ways o…Read more
  •  65
    Indeterminacy as Indecision, Lecture III: Indeterminacy as Indecision
    Journal of Philosophy 117 (11/12): 643-667. 2020.
    This lecture presents my own solution to the problem posed in Lecture I. Instead of a new theory of speech acts, it offers a new theory of the contents expressed by vague assertions, along the lines of the plan expressivism Allan Gibbard has advocated for normative language. On this view, the mental states we express in uttering vague sentences have a dual direction of fit: they jointly constrain the doxastic possibilities we recognize and our practical plans about how to draw boundaries. With t…Read more
  •  534
    Frege, Kant, and the logic in logicism
    Philosophical Review 111 (1): 25-65. 2002.
    Let me start with a well-known story. Kant held that logic and conceptual analysis alone cannot account for our knowledge of arithmetic: “however we might turn and twist our concepts, we could never, by the mere analysis of them, and without the aid of intuition, discover what is the sum [7+5]” (KrV, B16). Frege took himself to have shown that Kant was wrong about this. According to Frege’s logicist thesis, every arithmetical concept can be defined in purely logical terms, and every theorem of a…Read more
  • The Assessment Sensitivity of Knowledge Attributions
    Oxford Studies in Epistemology 1. 2006.
  •  145
    Vagueness and Thought (review)
    Philosophical Review 129 (1): 153-158. 2020.
  •  46
    On Probabilistic Knowledge
    Res Philosophica 97 (1): 97-108. 2020.
  •  109
    Vagueness as Indecision
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 90 (1): 255-283. 2016.
    This paper motivates and explores an expressivist theory of vagueness, modelled on Allan Gibbard’s normative expressivism. It shows how Chris Kennedy’s semantics for gradable adjectives can be adjusted to fit into a theory on Gibbardian lines, where assertions constrain not just possible worlds but plans for action. Vagueness, on this account, is literally indecision about where to draw lines. It is argued that the distinctive phenomena of vagueness, such as the intuition of tolerance, can be ex…Read more
  •  33
    Xiv *-making sense of relative truth
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 105 (1): 305-323. 2005.
  •  233
    Epistemic modals are assessment-sensitive
    In Andy Egan & Brian Weatherson (eds.), Epistemic Modality, Oxford University Press. 2011.
    By “epistemic modals,” I mean epistemic uses of modal words: adverbs like “necessarily,” “possibly,” and “probably,” adjectives like “necessary,” “possible,” and “probable,” and auxiliaries like “might,” “may,” “must,” and “could.” It is hard to say exactly what makes a word modal, or what makes a use of a modal epistemic, without begging the questions that will be our concern below, but some examples should get the idea across. If I say “Goldbach’s conjecture might be true, and it might be fals…Read more
  •  58
    Review: Potter, Reason's Nearest Kin: Philosophies of Arithmetic from Kant to Carnap
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 39 (3): 454-456. 2001.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Journal of the History of Philosophy 39.3 (2001) 454-456 [Access article in PDF] Michael Potter. Reason's Nearest Kin: Philosophies of Arithmetic from Kant to Carnap.New York: Oxford University Press, 2000. Pp. x + 305. Cloth, $45.00. This book tells the story of a remarkable series of answers to two related questions:(1) How can arithmetic be necessary and knowable a priori? [End Page 454](2) What accounts for the applicability of a…Read more
  •  441
    What Is Assertion
    In Jessica Brown & Herman Cappelen (eds.), Assertion, Oxford University Press. 2011.
    To assert something is to perform a certain kind of act. This act is different in kind both from other speech acts, like questions, requests, commands, promises, and apologies, and from acts that are not speech acts, like toast buttering and inarticulate yodeling. My question, then is this: what features of an act qualify it as an assertion, and not one of these other kinds of act? To focus on a particular example: in uttering “Bill will close the window,” one might be practicing English pronunc…Read more
  •  83
    Replies to Raffman, Stanley, and Wright
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 92 (1): 197-202. 2016.
  •  62
    Facing Facts (review)
    Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 200208. 2002.
  •  193
    Boghossian, Bellarmine, and Bayes
    Philosophical Studies 141 (3): 391-398. 2008.
    As Paul Boghossian sees it, postmodernist relativists and constructivists are paralyzed by a “fear of knowledge.” For example, they lack the courage to say, in the face of the Lakotas’ claim that their ancestors came from inside the earth, that it is a matter of known fact that their ancestors came across the Bering Strait. To avoid this, they accept the nonconfrontational view Boghossian calls..
  •  269
    Truth in the Garden of Forking Paths
    In Manuel García-Carpintero & Max Kölbel (eds.), Relative Truth, Oxford University Press. pp. 81--102. 2008.
    From García-Carpintero and Kölbel, eds, Relative Truth
  •  14
    Reason's Nearest Kin: Philosophies of Arithmetic from Kant to Carnap (review)
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 39 (3): 454-456. 2001.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Journal of the History of Philosophy 39.3 (2001) 454-456 [Access article in PDF] Michael Potter. Reason's Nearest Kin: Philosophies of Arithmetic from Kant to Carnap.New York: Oxford University Press, 2000. Pp. x + 305. Cloth, $45.00. This book tells the story of a remarkable series of answers to two related questions:(1) How can arithmetic be necessary and knowable a priori? [End Page 454](2) What accounts for the applicability of a…Read more
  •  578
    Making sense of relative truth
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 105 (3). 2005.
    The goal of this paper is to make sense of relativism about truth. There are two key ideas. (1) To be a relativist about truth is to allow that a sentence or proposition might be assessment-sensitive: that is, its truth value might vary with the context of assessment as well as the context of use. (2) Making sense of relativism is a matter of understanding what it would be to commit oneself to the truth of an assessment-sensitive sentence or proposition.
  •  252
    I want to discuss a puzzle about the semantics of epistemic modals, like “It might be the case that” as it occurs in “It might be the case that Goldbach’s conjecture is false.”1 I’ll argue that the puzzle cannot be adequately explained on standard accounts of the semantics of epistemic modals, and that a proper solution requires relativizing utterance truth to a context of assessment, a semantic device whose utility and coherence I have defended elsewhere for future contingents (MacFarlane..
  •  880
    Ifs and Oughts
    Journal of Philosophy 107 (3): 115-143. 2010.
    We consider a paradox involving indicative conditionals (‘ifs’) and deontic modals (‘oughts’). After considering and rejecting several standard options for resolv- ing the paradox—including rejecting various premises, positing an ambiguity or hidden contextual sensitivity, and positing a non-obvious logical form—we offer a semantics for deontic modals and indicative conditionals that resolves the paradox by making modus ponens invalid. We argue that this is a result to be welcomed on independent…Read more
  •  234
    Semantic Minimalism and Nonindexical Contextualism
    In Gerhard Preyer & Georg Peter (eds.), Context-Sensitivity and Semantic Minimalism: New Essays on Semantics and Pragmatics, Oxford University Press Uk. pp. 240--250. 2007.
    According to Semantic Minimalism, every use of "Chiara is tall" (fixing the girl and the time) semantically expresses the same proposition, the proposition that Chiara is (just plain) tall. Given standard assumptions, this proposition ought to have an intension (a function from possible worlds to truth values). However, speakers tend to reject questions that presuppose that it does. I suggest that semantic minimalists might address this problem by adopting a form of "nonindexical contextualism,"…Read more