CV
Belfast, United Kingdom of Great Britain and Northern Ireland
PhilPapers Editorships
Philosophy of History
  • Legal consciousness : a metahistory
    In Maksymilian Del Mar & Michael Lobban (eds.), Law in theory and history: new essays on a neglected dialogue, Hart Publishing. 2016.
  •  2
    This chapter contains sections titled: References.
  •  17
    Three Philosophical Moralists: Mill, Kant and Sartre. An Introduction to Ethics
    Philosophical Quarterly 41 (162): 116-117. 1991.
  •  5
    Value and Justification: The Foundations of Liberal Theory (review)
    Philosophical Studies (Dublin) 33 353-356. 1991.
  •  23
    Traditions in Philosophy of History
    Maynooth Philosophical Papers 9 59-79. 2018.
    I summarize the history of twentieth-century theorizing about history by historians and by philosophers of different traditions. I clarify the nature of ‘analytical’ philosophy, with philosophical arguments imagined to exist in a shared atemporal space. Analytical philosophy of history largely presupposed David Hume’s empiricism, explicit in Carl Hempel’s 1942 analysis of historical explanation as causal. Others argued for reasons instead, but by 1965 analytical philosophers were analysing histo…Read more
  •  16
    Value and Justification
    Philosophical Studies (Dublin) 33 353-356. 1991.
  •  34
    The Normativity of Logic in the History of Ideas
    Intellectual History Review 21 (1): 3-13. 2011.
    (2011). The Normativity of Logic in the History of Ideas. Intellectual History Review: Vol. 21, Post-Analytic Hermeneutics: Themes from Mark Bevir's Philosophy of History, pp. 3-13. doi: 10.1080/17496977.2011.546631
  •  14
    Philosophical Confidence
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Lecture Series 22 71-79. 1987.
    Analytical philosophers, if they are true to their training, never forget the first lesson of analytical philosophy: philosophers have no moral authority.In so far as analytical philosophers believe this, they find it easy to live with. For them even to assert, let alone successfully lay claim to, moral authority would require, first, hard work of some non-analytical and probably mistaken kind and, secondly, personality traits of leadership or confidence or even charisma, which philosophers may …Read more
  •  23
    Value and Justification (review)
    Philosophical Studies (Dublin) 33 353-356. 1991.
  •  94
    Paul A. Roth and the Revival of Analytical Philosophy of History
    Journal of the Philosophy of History 14 (1): 104-117. 2018.
    Krzysztof Brzechczyn’s important collection around Roth’s “revival” stimulates thought about the approaches adopted by analytical philosophers of history. Roth revives Danto’s 1965 pragmatic “constructivist” insights: in a narrative, earlier “events under a description” are described in terms of possibly unknowable later ones and, following Mink, in terms of possibly unknowable later concepts. Roth thinks of the resulting narrative explanation as justified in virtue of its constituting the objec…Read more
  •  22
    Discontinuity Pragmatically Framed
    Journal of the Philosophy of History 11 (2): 127-148. 2017.
    _ Source: _Volume 11, Issue 2, pp 127 - 148 This is an attempt to discover and clarify the philosophical nature of what Eelco Runia claims to be his new and up-to-date philosophy of history, a programme offered in his 2014 book _Moved by the Past: Discontinuity and Historical Mutation_. His suggestion that his argument is a “dance” is taken seriously, and following an analysis of historical “meaning” and its time-extended nature it is argued that the book’s presentation commits Runia to a concep…Read more
  •  14
    The historical profession is not noted for examining its own methodologies. Indeed, most historians are averse to historical theory. In "Historical Judgement" Jonathan Gorman's response to this state of affairs is to argue that if we want to characterize a discipline, we need to look to persons who successfully occupy the role of being practitioners of that discipline. So to model historiography we must do so from the views of historians. Gorman begins by showing what it is to model a discipline…Read more
  •  32
    In "Rights and Reason", Jonathan Gorman sets discussion of the 'rights debate' within a wide-ranging philosophical and historical framework. Drawing on positions in epistemology, metaphysics and the theory of human nature as well as on the ideas of canonical thinkers, Gorman provides an introduction to the philosophy of rights that is firmly grounded in the history of philosophy as well as the concerns of contemporary political and legal philosophy. The book gives readers a clear sense that, jus…Read more
  • Review: Philosophical Fascination with Whole Historical Texts (review)
    History and Theory 36 (3): 406-415. 1997.
  •  1
    KNOWLES, D.-Political Philosophy
    Philosophical Books 44 (2): 185-186. 2003.
  •  10
    Review: Reviews (review)
    Philosophy 80 (312). 2005.
  • Review: Freedom and History (review)
    History and Theory 39 (2): 251-262. 2000.
  • Review (review)
    History and Theory 30 356-368. 1991.
  • Review (review)
    History and Theory 26 99-114. 1987.
  •  11
    Political Disagreement (review)
    Philosophical Books 36 (3): 206-207. 1995.
  •  10
    Book reviews (review)
    British Journal of Aesthetics 20 (2): 187-189. 1980.
  •  66
    Objectivity and truth in history
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 17 (1-4). 1974.
    Examples of historical writing are analysed in detail, and it is demonstrated that, with respect to the statements which appear in historical accounts, their truth and value-freedom are neither necessary nor sufficient for the relative acceptability of historical accounts. What is both necessary and sufficient is the acceptability of the selection of statements involved, and it is shown that history can be objective only if the acceptability of selection can be made on the basis of a rational cr…Read more
  •  20
    Justifying Historical Descriptions
    Philosophical Books 26 (4): 246-248. 1985.
  •  30
    The Need for Quinean Pragmatism in the Theory of History
    European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy 8 (2). 2016.
    I present the history of philosophy, and history more generally, as a context of ideas, with respect to which philosophers and historians share concerns about the meaning of the texts they both use, and where for some there is a principled contrast between seeing meaning in quasi-mathematical terms (“a philosophical stance”) or in terms of context (“a historical stance”). I introduce this imagined (but not imaginary) world of ideas as temporally extended. Returning to my early research into the …Read more
  •  62
    Historians and Their Duties
    History and Theory 43 (4): 103-117. 2004.
    We need to specify what ethical responsibility historians, as historians, owe, and to whom. We should distinguish between natural duties and obligations, and recognize that historians' ethical responsibility is of the latter kind. We can discover this responsibility by using the concept of “accountability”. Historical knowledge is central. Historians' central ethical responsibility is that they ought to tell the objective truth. This is not a duty shared with everybody, for the right to truth va…Read more
  • Review (review)
    History and Theory 33 230-241. 1994.
  •  1
    Book reviews (review)
    with Babette E. Babich, Alison Ainley, John Dillon, Alan P. F. Sell, David Archard, Paul O'Grady, Brian O'Connor, John E. Chisholm, Fiachra Long, Christopher McKnight, and Kathleen Nutt
    International Journal of Philosophical Studies 1 (1): 135-162. 1993.
  •  13
    Our Knowledge of the Past: A Philosophy of Historiography (review)
    Philosophy 80 (2): 292-300. 2005.