•  134
    How could ectogestative technology disrupt gender roles, parenting practices, and concepts such as ‘birth’, ‘body’, or ‘parent’? In this chapter, we situate this emerging technology in the context of the history of reproductive technologies and analyse the potential social and conceptual disruptions to which it could contribute. An ectogestative device, better known as ‘artificial womb’, enables the extra-uterine gestation of a human being, or mammal more generally. It is currently developed wit…Read more
  •  111
    The dynamics of moral progress
    Ratio 32 (4): 300-311. 2019.
    Assuming that there is moral progress, and assuming that the abolition of slavery is an example of it, how does moral progress occur? Is it mainly driven by specific individuals who have gained new moral insights, or by changes in the socio‐economic and epistemic conditions in which agents morally judge the norms and practices of their society, and act upon these judgements? In this paper, I argue that moral progress is a complex process in which changes at the level of belief and changes at the…Read more
  •  61
    Current academic philosophy is being challenged from several angles. Subdisciplinary specialisations often make it challenging to articulate philosophy’s relevance for the societal questions of our day. Additionally, the success of the ‘scientific method’ puts pressure on philosophers to articulate their methods and specify how these can be successful. How does philosophical progress come about? What can philosophy contribute to our understanding of today’s world? Moreover, can it also contribut…Read more
  •  48
    Possibilities of Moral Progress in the Face of Evolution
    Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 20 (1): 39-54. 2017.
    Evolutionary accounts of the origin of human morality may be speculative to some extent, but they contain some very plausible claims, such as the claim that ethics evolved as a response to the demands of group living. Regarding the phenomenon of moral progress, it has been argued both that it is ruled out by an evolutionary approach, and that it can be explained by it. It has even been claimed that an evolutionary account has the potential to advance progress in the moral domain. This paper expl…Read more
  •  48
    Sinnott-Armstrong’s Empirical Challenge to Moral Intuitionism: a Novel Critique
    Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 20 (4): 829-842. 2017.
    This paper provides a novel critique of Walter Sinnott-Armstrong’s influential argument against epistemological moral intuitionism, the view that some people are non-inferentially justified in believing some moral propositions. At the beginning of the twenty-first century, this view experienced a revival, which coincided with an increasing interest in empirical research on intuitions. The results of that research are seen by some as casting serious doubt on the reliability of our moral intuition…Read more
  •  24
    On Moral Certainty, Justification and Practice presents a view of morality that is inspired by the later Wittgenstein. Hermann explores the ethical implications of Wittgenstein's remarks on doubt, justification, rule-following, certainty and training, offering an alternative to interpretations of Wittgenstein's work that view it as being intrinsically ethical. The book scrutinises cases in which doubt and justification do not make sense, and contrasts certain justificatory demands made by philos…Read more
  •  12
    Brede moraal, brede rede, brede intuïtie?
    Algemeen Nederlands Tijdschrift voor Wijsbegeerte 114 (1): 37-41. 2022.
    Amsterdam University Press is a leading publisher of academic books, journals and textbooks in the Humanities and Social Sciences. Our aim is to make current research available to scholars, students, innovators, and the general public. AUP stands for scholarly excellence, global presence, and engagement with the international academic community.
  •  11
    St. Anselm on Free Choice and the Power to Sin
    In Michael Bruce & Steven Barbone (eds.), Just the Arguments, Wiley‐blackwell. 2011-09-16.
  •  5
    Structure and composition analysis of the phases in the system Th-Pd-B-C containing superconductors with T c = 14.5 K and T c = 21 K (review)
    with H. W. Zandbergen, T. J. Gortenmulder, J. L. Sarrac, J. C. Harrison, M. C. de Andrade, S. H. Han, Z. Fisk, M. B. Maple, and R. J. Cava
    Several specimens in the system Th-Pd-B-C with nominal compositions ThPd3B2C and ThPd3B3C, containing superconducting phases exhibiting Tc's of 14.5 K and 21 K, have been studied with EPMA, electron diffraction, EDX element analysis and HREM. A number of phases have been observed: ThPd2B2C, I-centered tetragonal, a = 0.375, c = 1.07 nm, which can be related to the Tc of 14.5 K; ThPd0.65B4.7, P-type cubic, a = 0.42 nm, with short-range ordered superstructure resulting in diffuse streaks in the el…Read more
  •  3
    Editorial
    Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 20 (4): 705-707. 2017.
  •  2
    HREM on T c =14.5 K superconducting ThPd 2 B 2-x C
    with H. W. Zandbergen, E. J. van Zwet, J. C. Sarrac, M. C. de Andrade, S. H. Han, Z. Fisk, M. B. Maple, and R. J. Cava
    The compound ThPd2B2C has been studied with high-resolution electron microscopy and electron diffraction. ThPd2B2-xC adopts the LuNi2B2C structure with a layer sequence n in which the B composition and the exact position of the C are still uncertain. No intergrowths or planar defects are observed. The c-axis in the thinner parts of the crystals was observed to decrease up to about 0.5 nm when irradiated by the electron beam. © 1994.
  •  1
    Pufendorf and Natural Law
    Philosophical Forum 42 (3): 299-300. 2011.