•  39
    An outstanding reference source for the wide range of philosophical contributions made by women writing in Europe from about 1560 to 1780. It shows the range of genres and methods used by women writing in these centuries in Europe, thus encouraging an expanded understanding of our historical canon.
  •  32
    Philosophy, Academic and Public
    Precollege Philosophy and Public Practice 4 91-109. 2022.
    In 2020, the University of Pennsylvania instituted a graduate certificate in public philosophy. In many ways, this certificate formalized and recognized the public engagement work that graduate students in the philosophy department and beyond had been involved with for some years. One element of the certificate, however, was pivotal in moving our work in public philosophy forward in important ways. This element is the research seminar in public philosophy. In this paper, we recount the motivatio…Read more
  •  9
  •  36
    In this chapter, I examine similarities and divergences between Du Châtelet and Descartes on their endorsement of the use of hypotheses in science, using the work of Condillac to locate them in his scheme of systematizers. I conclude that, while Du Châtelet is still clearly a natural philosopher, as opposed to modern scientist, her conception of hypotheses is considerably more modern than is Descartes’, a difference that finds its roots in their divergence on the nature of first principles.
  •  15
    Critical Notice (review)
    Philosophical Inquiry 26 (4): 131-138. 2004.
  •  1
    Generation and the Individual in Descartes, Malebranche and Leibniz
    Dissertation, University of Toronto (Canada). 2001.
    This dissertation is an examination of the emergence of the preformation doctrine of generation in three early modern philosophers: Descartes, Malebranche and Leibniz. Received wisdom on this question maintains that the preformation doctrine became so popular in the seventeenth century because it seemed most capable of explaining generation of living beings within the limits of the reigning mechanical philosophy. This dissertation considers another motivation, generally neglected by commentators…Read more
  •  4224
    Atomism, Monism, and Causation in the Natural Philosophy of Margaret Cavendish
    Oxford Studies in Early Modern Philosophy 3 199-240. 2006.
    Between 1653 and 1655 Margaret Cavendish makes a radical transition in her theory of matter, rejecting her earlier atomism in favour of an infinitely-extended and infinitely-divisible material plenum, with matter being ubiquitously self-moving, sensing, and rational. It is unclear, however, if Cavendish can actually dispense of atomism. One of her arguments against atomism, for example, depends upon the created world being harmonious and orderly, a premise Cavendish herself repeatedly undermines…Read more
  •  786
    Du Châtelet and Descartes on the Role of Hypothesis and Metaphysics in Science
    In Eileen O'Neill & Marcy Lascano (eds.), Feminism and the History of Philosophy, Kluwer Academic Publishers. forthcoming.
    In this chapter, I examine similarities and divergences between Du Châtelet and Descartes on their endorsement of the use of hypotheses in science, using the work of Condillac to locate them in his scheme of systematizers. I conclude that, while Du Châtelet is still clearly a natural philosopher, as opposed to modern scientist, her conception of hypotheses is considerably more modern than is Descartes’, a difference that finds its roots in their divergence on the nature of first principles.
  •  32
    Review of Desmond M. Clarke, Descartes: A Biography (review)
    Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2006 (11). 2006.
  •  129
    Supernaturalism, occasionalism, and preformation in Malebranche
    Perspectives on Science 11 (4): 443-483. 2003.
    Malebranche is both an occasionalist and an advocate of the preformationist theory of generation. One might expect this given that he is a mechanist: passive matter cannot be the source of its own motion and so requires God to move it (occasionalism); and such matter, moving according to a few simple laws of motion, could never fashion something as complex as a living being, and so organisms must be fashioned by God at Creation (preformationism). This expectation finds a challenge in Kant's depi…Read more
  •  1625
    Margaret Cavendish on the relation between God and world
    Philosophy Compass 4 (3): 421-438. 2009.
    It has often been noted that Margaret Cavendish discusses God in her writings on natural philosophy far more than one might think she ought to given her explicit claim that a study of God belongs to theology which is to be kept strictly separate from studies in natural philosophy. In this article, I examine one way in which God enters substantially into her natural philosophy, namely the role he plays in her particular version of teleology. I conclude that, while Cavendish has some resources wit…Read more
  •  54
    Critical Notice (review)
    Philosophical Inquiry 26 (4): 131-138. 2004.
    Critical notice of Jacqueline Broad's Women Philosophers of the Seventeenth Century (CUP, 2002).
  •  1568
    Descartes on the Theory of Life and Methodology in the Life Sciences
    In Peter Distelzweig, Evan Ragland & Benjamin Goldberg (eds.), Early Modern Medicine and Natural Philosophy, Springer. pp. 141-72. 2016.
    As a practicing life scientist, Descartes must have a theory of what it means to be a living being. In this paper, I provide an account of what his theoretical conception of living bodies must be. I then show that this conception might well run afoul of his rejection of final causal explanations in natural philosophy. Nonetheless, I show how Descartes might have made use of such explanations as merely hypothetical, even though he explicitly blocks this move. I conclude by suggesting that there i…Read more
  •  40
    Review of Margaret Cavendish, Observations Upon Experimental Philosophy (review)
    Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2002 (7). 2002.
  •  2044
    In this paper, I consider Descartes’ Sixth Meditation dropsy passage on the difference between the human body considered in itself and the human composite of mind and body. I do so as a way of illuminating some features of Descartes’ broader thinking about teleology, including the role of teleological explanations in physiology. I use the writings on teleology of some ancient authors for the conceptual (but not historical) help they can provide in helping us to think about the Sixth Meditation p…Read more
  •  1169
    In this paper, I consider Mary Astell's contributions to the history of feminism, noting her grounding in and departure from Cartesianism and its relation to women.
  •  288
    Descartes’s Method of Doubt (review)
    Dialogue 45 (2): 404. 2006.
  •  72
    Emilie Du Châtelet: Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2013.
    A survey article on the metaphysics, physics and methodology of Du Châtelet.
  •  414
    Women and Liberty, 1600-1800: Philosophical Essays (edited book)
    Oxford University Press. 2017.
    There have been many different historical-intellectual accounts of the shaping and development of concepts of liberty in pre-Enlightenment Europe. This volume is unique for addressing the subject of liberty principally as it is discussed in the writings of women philosophers, and as it is theorized with respect to women and their lives, during this period. The volume covers ethical, political, metaphysical, and religious notions of liberty, with some chapters discussing women's ideas about the m…Read more
  •  70
    Review of Sarah Hutton, Anne Conway: A Woman Philosopher (review)
    Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2005 (7). 2005.