•  12
    Real ImaginingsMemesis As Make-Believe
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 51 (2): 389. 1991.
  • Marie-laure Ryan
    Semiotica 103 (3/4): 349-367. 1995.
  •  169
    On Kendall Walton's Mimesis as Make-BelieveMemesis As Make-Believe (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 51 (2): 383. 1991.
  •  56
    Mimesis as Make-Believe: On the Foundations of the Representational Arts
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 49 (2): 161-166. 1990.
  •  95
    Aesthetic Properties: Context Dependent and Perceptual
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 78 (1): 79-84. 2020.
    The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, Volume 78, Issue 1, Page 79-84, Winter 2020.
  •  6
    Reply to Reviewers
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 51 (2): 413-431. 1991.
  •  26
    Metaphor and prop oriented make-believe
    In Mark Eli Kalderon (ed.), Fictionalism in Metaphysics, Clarendon Press. 2005.
    Peer Reviewed.
  •  40
    Comments on Mimesis as Make-BelieveMemesis As Make-Believe (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 51 (2): 395. 1991.
  •  42
    A Note on Mimesis as Make-BelieveMemesis As Make-Believe (review)
    with Richard Wollheim
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 51 (2): 401. 1991.
  •  13
    Realist theories about fictional entities must explain the fact that, in ordinary contexts people deny, apparently in all seriousness, that there are such things as the Big Bad Wolf and Santa Claus. The usual explanation treats these denials as involving restricted quantification: The speaker is said to be denying only that the Big Bad Wolf and Santa Claus are to be found among real or actual things, not that there are no such things at all. This is unconvincing. The denials may just as naturall…Read more
  •  394
    Metaphor and Prop Oriented Make‐Believe
    European Journal of Philosophy 1 (1): 39-57. 1993.
    Peer Reviewed.
  •  73
    Comment on Catherine Wilson, 'Grief and the Poet'
    British Journal of Aesthetics 53 (1): 113-115. 2013.
  •  398
    I propose a way of understanding empathy on which it does not necessarily involve any-thing like thinking oneself into another’s shoes, or any imagining at all. Briefly, the empa-thizer uses an aspect of her own mental state as a sample, expressed by means of a phenomenal concept, to understand the other person. This account does a better job of explaining the connection between empathetic experiences and the objects of empathy than most traditional ones do. And it helps to clarify the relations…Read more
  •  1029
  •  5
    Memesis As Make-Believe
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 51 (2): 407-411. 1991.
  •  55
    Looking Again through Photographs: A Response to Edwin Martin
    Critical Inquiry 12 (4): 801-808. 1986.
    My great-grandfather died before I was born. He never saw me. But I see him occasionally—when I look at photographs of him. They are not great photographs, by any means, but like most photographs they are transparent. We see things through them.Edwin Martin objects. His response consists largely of citing examples of things which, he thinks, are obviously not transparent, and declaring that he finds no relevant difference between them and photographs: once we slide down the slippery slope as far…Read more
  •  11
    Style and the Products and Processes of Art
    In Leonard B. Meyer & Berel Lang (eds.), The Concept of Style, University of Pennsylvania Press. pp. 45--66. 1979.
  •  1889
    Fearing fictions
    Journal of Philosophy 75 (1): 5-27. 1978.
  •  122
    The reader's access to the fictional world of a novel is mediated by the narrator, when there is one; the fictional world is presented from the narrator's perspective. do depictions ever have anything comparable to narrators? apparent artists sometimes have a certain perspective on the fictional world. but they don't mediate our access to it; the fictional world is presented independently of their perspective on it. depictions do present fictional worlds from certain perspectives, but not usuall…Read more
  •  155
    Are Representations Symbols?
    The Monist 58 (2): 236-254. 1974.
    The representational arts seem friendly territory for “symbol” theories of aesthetics. Much of the initial resistance one may feel to the idea that a Mondrian composition or a Scarlatti sonata is a symbol evaporates when we switch to a portrait of Mozart, Michelangelo’s Pietá, or Dickens’s A Tale of Two Cities. These representational works have reference to things outside themselves. The portrait is a picture of Mozart; the Pietá is a sculpture of Christ and his Mother; A Tale of Two Cities is a…Read more
  •  55
    Not a leg to stand on the roof on
    Journal of Philosophy 70 (19): 725-726. 1973.
  •  1092
    Mimesis as Make-Believe is important reading for everyone interested in the workings of representational art.
  •  32
    Review of Works and Worlds of Arts by Nicholas Wolterstorff (review)
    Journal of Philosophy 80 (3): 179-193. 1983.
  •  250
    How remote are fictional worlds from the real world?
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 37 (1): 11-23. 1978.
  •  172
    Sports and competitive games of many kinds—from tag to chess to baseball—are often occasions for make-believe. To participate either as a competitor or as a spectator is frequently to engage in pretense. The activities of playing and watching games have this in common with appreciating works of fiction and participating in children’s make-believe activities, although the make-believe in sports, masked by real interests and concerns, is less obvious than it is in the other cases. What is most int…Read more