•  865
    The Barber, Russell's Paradox, Catch-22, God, Contradiction, and More
    In Graham Priest, J. C. Beall & Bradley Armour-Garb (eds.), The Law of Non-Contradiction, Clarendon Press. pp. 295--313. 2004.
    outrageous remarks about contradictions. Perhaps the most striking remark he makes is that they are not false. This claim first appears in his early notebooks (Wittgenstein 1960, p.108). In the Tractatus, Wittgenstein argued that contradictions (like tautologies) are not statements (Sätze) and hence are not false (or true). This is a consequence of his theory that genuine statements are pictures.
  •  176
    A consistent way with paradox
    Philosophical Studies 144 (3). 2009.
    Consideration of a paradox originally discovered by John Buridan provides a springboard for a general solution to paradoxes within the Liar family. The solution rests on a philosophical defence of truth-value-gaps and is consistent (non-dialetheist), avoids ‘revenge’ problems, imports no ad hoc assumptions, is not applicable to only a proper subset of the semantic paradoxes and implies no restriction of the expressive capacities of language.
  •  162
    How to boil a live frog
    Analysis 60 (2). 2000.
  •  129
    Wittgenstein's ph.D viva—a re-creation
    Philosophy 74 (4): 499-513. 1999.
  •  129
    Review: Wittgenstein: Meaning and Judgement (review)
    Mind 115 (458): 437-439. 2006.
  •  120
    How original a work is the tractatus logico-philosophicus?
    Philosophy 77 (3): 421-446. 2002.
    Wittgenstein's Tractatus is widely regarded as a masterpiece, a brilliant, if flawed attempt to achieve an ‘unassailable and definitive … final solution’ to a wide range of philosophical problems. Yet, in a 1931 notebook, Wittgenstein confesses: ‘I think there is some truth in my idea that I am really only reproductive in my thinking. I think I have never invented a line of thinking but that it was always provided for me by someone else’. This disarming self-assessment is, I believe accurate. Th…Read more
  •  120
    Is there a key for ‘translating' some set-theoretical paradoxes into counterpart semantical paradoxes and vice-versa? There is, and this encourages the hope of a unified solution. The solution turns not on inventing new axioms that do not entail contradiction, but on imposing a completely intuitive restriction on the comprehension axiom of naive set theory in order to avoid illegitimate (circular) stipulation
  •  106
    The Sorites is nonsense disguised by a fallacy
    Analysis 72 (1): 61-65. 2012.
    It is uncontroversial that, on any run through a Sorites series, a subject, at some point, switches from an ‘F’ verdict on one exhibit to a non-‘F’ verdict on the next. (Where this ‘cut-off’ point occurs tend to differ from trial to trial.) It is a fallacy to infer that there must be a cut-off point simpliciter between F items and non-F items. The transition is from firm ground to swamp. In the Sorites reasoning, some conditionals of the form ‘If Item n is F, then Item n + 1 is F’ are not false …Read more
  •  106
    The Indefinability of “One”
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 31 (1): 29-42. 2002.
    Logicism is one of the great reductionist projects. Numbers and the relationships in which they stand may seem to possess suspect ontological credentials – to be entia non grata – and, further, to be beyond the reach of knowledge. In seeking to reduce mathematics to a small set of principles that form the logical basis of all reasoning, logicism holds out the prospect of ontological economy and epistemological security. This paper attempts to show that a fundamental logicist project, that of…Read more
  •  103
    Pierre and circumspection in belief-formation
    Analysis 69 (4): 653-655. 2009.
    In a well-known story constructed by Saul Kripke , Pierre, a rational but monolingual Frenchman who has never visited England, acquires, on the evidence of many magazine pictures of London, the belief that London is beautiful. He is happy to declare ‘Londres est jolie’. Pierre eventually moves to England and settles in one of the seedier areas of London, travelling only to comparably shabby neighbourhoods. He learns English by immersion, though he does not realize that ‘London’ and ‘Londres’ are…Read more
  •  100
    False stipulation and semantical paradox
    Analysis 46 (4): 192-195. 1986.
  •  100
    A non-theistic cosmology and natural history
    Analysis 66 (3): 256-260. 2006.
    The plausibility of the theory of evolution depends on abandoning the assumption of a unique 'big bang' ex nihilo marking the beginning of the universe.
  •  98
    Introduction
    The Monist 88 (1): 3-10. 2005.
    According to some commentators, Wittgenstein’s Tractatus is all one big joke: we plough through the text trying to extract the sense out of each spare and heroic proposition, only to be told at the end, that anyone who understands the author will realize that all of his propositions are nonsensical and so are not even propositions. The whole work is a kind of hoax; the readers are ridiculed, but, with luck, will eventually have to laugh when they come to recognize that what they had taken for de…Read more
  •  95
    Wittgenstein and situation comedy
    Philosophia 37 (4): 605-627. 2009.
    Wittgenstein discusses speakers exploiting context to inject meaning into the sentences that they use. One facet of situation comedy is context-injected ambiguity, where scriptwriters artfully construct situations such that, because of conflicting contextual clues, a character, though uttering a sentence that contains neither ambiguous words nor amphibolous contruction may plausibly be interpreted in at least two distinct ways. This highlights an important distinction between the (concise) sente…Read more
  •  92
    A syntactically correct number-specification may fail to specify any number due to underspecification. For similar reasons, although each sentence in the Yablo sequence is syntactically perfect, none yields a statement with any truth-value. As is true of all members of the Liar family, the sentences in the Yablo sequence are so constructed that the specification of their truth-conditions is vacuous; the Yablo sentences fail to yield statements. The ‘revenge’ problem is easily defused. The soluti…Read more
  •  92
    The development of wittgenstein's views on contradiction
    History and Philosophy of Logic 7 (1): 43-56. 1986.
    The views on contradiction and consistency that Wittgenstein expressed in his later writings have met with misunderstanding and almost uniform hositility. In this paper, I trace the roots of these views by attempting to show that, in his early writings, Wittgenstein accorded a ?unique status? to tautologies and contradictions, marking them off logically from genuine propositions. This is integral both to his Tractatus project of furnishing a theory of inference, and to the enterprise of explaini…Read more
  •  82
    The reasons of a materialist
    Philosophy 55 (April): 249-252. 1980.
  •  81
    Refuse disposal
    Analysis 62 (3). 2002.
  •  80
  •  71
    Spandrels of Truth * By JC BEALL
    Analysis 70 (3): 586-589. 2010.
    (No abstract is available for this citation)
  •  71
    Epimenides and Curry
    Analysis 46 (3). 1986.
  •  70
    Stephen Clark, the laws of logic and the sorites
    Philosophy 84 (1): 135-143. 2009.
    A standard method for refuting a set of claims is to show that it implies a contradiction. Stephen Clark questions this method on the grounds that the Law of Non-Contradiction, together with the other fundamental laws of logic do not accord with everyday reality. He accounts for vagueness by suggesting that, for any vague predicate 'F', an ordinary object is typically to some extent both F and not-F, and that objects do not change abruptly from being F to being not-F. I challenge Clark's 'decons…Read more
  •  67
    The adverbial theory of conceptual thought
    The Monist 65 (July): 379-392. 1982.
    Romane Clark has complained of the dissimilarity between Sellars’s treatment of conceptual thought and his treatment of sense impressions. For sense impressions are intrinsic to perceptions and, on Sellars’s view, both conceptual thought and perception are species of judgment. In the first section of this paper I want to raise a converse sort of complaint: Sellars offers an ‘adverbial’ theory of sense impressions and a similar account of conceptual thought. But this similarity of treatment is no…Read more
  •  66
    The title of this paper is 'quotation'
    Analysis 45 (3): 137-140. 1985.
  •  60
    Farewell to grelling
    Analysis 63 (1). 2003.