•  30
    Letters to the Editor
    with J. B. Schneewind, Paul Humphreys, Celia Wolf-Devine, George Graham, Daniel P. Anderson, Mary Ellen Waithe, Tibor R. Machan, and Jonathan E. Adler
    Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 69 (5). 1996.
  •  25
    Letters to the Editor
    Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 66 (1). 1992.
  •  9
    Review of Douglas N. Husak: Philosophy of criminal law (review)
    Ethics 99 (4): 953-954. 1989.
  •  43
    Letters to the Editor
    with Oskar Gruenwald, Lawrence M. Thomas, Robert L. Perea, Howard Stein, Bryan W. Van Norden, and Jennifer Uleman
    Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 70 (2). 1996.
  •  31
    Emotion, representation, and consciousness
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 23 (2): 204-205. 2000.
    Rolls's preliminary definitions of emotion and speculative restriction of consciousness, including emotional sentience, to humans, display behaviorist prejudice. Reinforcement and causation are not by themselves sufficient conceptual resources to define either emotion or the directedness of thought and motivated action. For any adequate definition of emotion or delimitation of consciousness, new physiology, such as Rolls is contributing to, and also the resources of other fields, will be require…Read more
  •  18
  •  50
    Review of Timothy Schroeder, Three Faces of Desire (review)
    Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2005 (9). 2005.
  •  46
    Hedonism as Metaphysics of Mind and Value
    Dissertation, Princeton University. 1986.
    I develop and defend a hedonistic view of the constitution of human subjectivity, agency and value, while disassociating it from utilitarian accounts of morality and from the view that only pleasure is desired. Chapter One motivates the general question, "What really is of value in human living?", and introduces evaluative hedonism as an answer to this question. Chapter Two argues against preference satisfaction accounts of pleasure and of welfare, and begins the explication and defense of the h…Read more
  •  45
    On distinguishing phenomenal consciousness from the representational functions of mind
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (2): 258-259. 1995.
    One can share Block's aim of distinguishing “phenomenal” experience from cognitive function and agree with much in his views, yet hold that the inclusion of representational content within phenomenal content, if only in certain spatial cases, obscures this distinction. It may also exclude some modular theories, although it is interestingly suggestive of what may be the limits of the phenomenal penetration of the representational mind.
  •  71
    Dopamine and serotonin: Integrating current affective engagement with longer-term goals
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 22 (3): 527-527. 1999.
    Interpreting VTA dopamine activity as a facilitator of affective engagement fits Depue & Collins's agency dimension of extraverted personality and also Watson's and Tellegen's (1985) engagement dimension of state mood. Serotonin, by turning down the gain on dopaminergic affective engagement, would permit already prepotent responses or habits to prevail against the behavior-switching incentive-simulation-driven temptations of the moment facilitated by fickle VTA DA. Intelligent switching between …Read more
  •  31
    Toward good and evil. Evolutionary approaches to aspects of human morality
    Journal of Consciousness Studies 7 (1-2): 1-2. 2000.
    Editorial Introduction to ‘Evolutionary Origins of Morality: Cross-Disciplinary Perspectives’. The four principal papers presented here, with interdisciplinary commentary discussion and their authors’ responses, represent contemporary approaches to an evolutionary understanding of morality -- of the origins from which, and the paths by which, aspects or components of human morality evolved and converged. Their authors come out of no single discipline or school, but represent rather a convergence…Read more
  •  49
    Human emotional experience is organized at multiple levels, only some of which are easily penetrable by or dependent on language. Affects connected with mammalian parental care seem involved in Anna Wierzbicka's example of the experience of Jesus in Gethsemane. However, such affects are not characterizable as she requires, using only NSM's short list of linguistic semantic universals. Following her methodology, even using an enriched NSM really exhaustive of linguistic semantic universals, may i…Read more
  •  133
    Pleasure
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2008.
    Pleasure, in the inclusive usages most important in moral psychology, ethical theory, and the studies of mind, includes all joy and gladness — all our feeling good, or happy. It is often contrasted with similarly inclusive pain, or suffering, which is similarly thought of as including all our feeling bad. Contemporary psychology similarly distinguishes between positive affect and negative affect.[1..
  •  79
    Four principal papers and a total of 43 peer commentaries on the evolutionary origins of morality. To what extent is human morality the outcome of a continuous development from motives, emotions and social behaviour found in nonhuman animals? Jerome Kagan, Hans Kummer, Peter Railton and others discuss the first principal paper by primatologists Jessica Flack and Frans de Waal. The second paper, by cultural anthropologist Christopher Boehm, synthesizes social science and biological evidence to su…Read more
  •  73
    Depue & Morrone-Strupinsky's (D&M-S's) language suggests that, unlike Kent Berridge, they may allow that the activity of a largely subcortical system, which is presumably often introspectively and cognitively inaccessible, constitutes affectively felt experience even when so. Such experience would then be phenomenally conscious without being reflexively conscious or cognitively access-conscious, to use distinctions formulated by the philosopher Ned Block.