•  15
    Through a curated selection of essays written over four decades by one of Australia’s leading philosophers, this collection demonstrates the impact of Continental philosophy on philosophical thought in Australia.
  • Remembering
    with C. B. Martin
    In Sven Bernecker & Fred I. Dretske (eds.), Knowledge: Readings in Contemporary Epistemology, Oxford University Press. 2000.
  •  23
    VESEY, G. N. A.: "The embodied mind" (review)
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 43 (n/a): 402. 1965.
  • La Caze, Marguerite, The Analytic Imaginary
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 81 (4): 611. 2003.
  • LEYDEN, W. VON - "Remembering" (review)
    Mind 71 (n/a): 277. 1962.
  •  12
  •  3
    Bonney on saying and disbelieving
    Analysis 27 (6): 184-186. 1967.
  •  14
    Judgment After Arendt
    Routledge. 2007.
    Pt. I. Appearances of thought. 1. Appearances. 2. Thinking. 3. Recall -- Pt. II. Thinking with others. 4. By metaphor. 5. Conversing. 6. Absence -- Pt. III. Willing myths. 7. Being willing. 8. Resolving will. 9. Commandment -- Pt. IV. Judgment. 10. Process and judgment. 11. Working magic. 12. Willing thought.
  •  30
    9 page
  • NEEDLEMAN, J.: "The Heart of Philosophy" (review)
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 63 (n/a): 375. 1985.
  •  9
    FRENCH, P. S., et. al., , "Midwest Studies in Philosophy", Vol. IV, Studies in Metaphysics (review)
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 59 (n/a): 222. 1981.
  • DURRANT, R. G. : "Essays in Honour of Gwen Taylor" (review)
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 62 (n/a): 188. 1984.
  •  20
    Sting of Reason
    Parrhesia 13 82. 2011.
  •  18
    Stories, Pictures, Arguments
    Philosophy 62 (240). 1987.
    There is a tradition of philosophy—a conception we can easily under-stand as a limit of a tendency of our own thinking—that philosophy consists only of argument. The rest of the vast prepon-derance of words in philosophical texts is simply embroidery. ‘Naturally’, it will be conceded, actual philosophy books contain more or less of verbal pictures, words and phrases whose purpose is to evoke images, and many stories—examples, hard cases for definitions, and 4 anecdotes. These, it will be said, ‘…Read more
  • Subjecting and Objecting
    Philosophy 60 (231): 138-140. 1985.
  • In Sensible Judgment
    Symposium: Canadian Journal of Continental Philosophy/Revue canadienne de philosophie continentale 16 (1): 203-225. 2012.
    The article focuses on the support to the position of Hannah Arendt that taste and feelings have roles in having sensible judgment. It mentions the pleasure that are derived from judgment such as aesthetic judgment and judging what is right. It states that Arendt argues that judgment should be used to defeat moral epithets.
  •  106
    David Armstrong and perception
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 41 (1): 80-88. 1963.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  870
    Remembering
    with C. B. Martin
    Philosophical Review 75 (April): 161-96. 1966.
  •  41
    Popper's problem of an empirical basis
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 46 (3). 1968.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  29
    I exist
    Mind 76 (304): 583-586. 1967.
  •  79
    Bonney on Saying and Disbelieving
    Analysis 27 (6). 1967.
  •  39
    Some recollections of Ryle and remarks on his notion of negative action
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 60 (3). 1982.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  9
    In Sensible Judgement
    Symposium: Canadian Journal of Continental Philosophy/Revue canadienne de philosophie continentale 16 (1): 203-225. 2012.
    Only in being pleased at what is done can I judge it as right. Kant is correct, nevertheless, then my motive is not the object of my judgment's concern. In working to make a good judgment, it is not pleasure but die right result that one seeks. In taking the jury's decision to be right, one is pleased at it—one takes pleasure in it. At the same time, it would shift attention from judgment's proper object to find the point of die justice of the decision in one's having been pleased.
  •  7
    Developing a reading of some of Beauvoir and Sartre's most influential writings in philosophy, Max Deutscher explores contemporary philosophy in the light of the phenomenological tradition within which Being and Nothingness and The Second Sex occurred as striking events operating on the border of the modern and the 'post-modern'. Deutscher traces the shifts of genre that produce their gendered philosophies, and responds in terms of contemporary experience to the mood and the arguments of their w…Read more
  •  24
    ARMSTRONG, D. M.: "Belief, Truth and Knowledge"
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 54 (n/a): 162. 1976.
  •  26
    Forms, Qualities, Resemblance
    Philosophy 67 (262). 1992.
    Long after we have abandoned belief in a Cosmic Law Giver, still we cling to the word ‘law’ in science. It is in this same way that we cannot let go of the substantializing and pluralizing ‘universal’, even though its literal sense indicates a kind of turning, a ‘one-turning’, rather than a kind of thing . Yet ‘the problem of Universals’ is supposed to have become, again, a ‘compulsory examination question’ for philosophers. Let us reveal how this tradition begins for us
  •  2
    Remembering "remembering"
    In John Heil (ed.), Identity, Cause, and Mind, Kluwer Academic Publishers. 1989.
  •  1050
    “Il n’y a pas de hors-texte”—Once More
    Symposium 18 (2): 98-124. 2014.
    Spivak translates Derrida’s “il n’y a pas de hors-texte” as “there is nothing outside the text.” By considering how the aphorism works within his study of Rousseau on sexual and textual supplements, and by reviewing related expressions in French, a mistranslation is revealed. This is not a simple error, however. The distortion is generated by Derrida’s own broader context. We must not only distinguish signification from reference but also place the aphorism within Derrida’s allusion, in the firs…Read more