•  183
    Representationalism and Husserlian Phenomenology
    Husserl Studies 27 (3): 197-215. 2011.
    According to contemporary representationalism, phenomenal qualia—of specifically sensory experiences—supervene on representational content. Most arguments for representationalism share a common, phenomenological premise: the so-called “transparency thesis.” According to the transparency thesis, it is difficult—if not impossible—to distinguish the quality or character of experiencing an object from the perceived properties of that object. In this paper, I show that Husserl would react negatively …Read more
  •  58
    Dan Zahavi, Subjectivity and Selfhood. (review)
    Husserl Studies 25 (3): 261-266. 2009.
  •  104
    The Paradox of Subjectivity
    Husserl Studies 21 (2): 139-144. 2005.
    In this elegant, smoothly written book, David Carr provides nothing less than a defense of both Kantian and Husserlian versions of transcendental philosophy against Heidegger’s critique of metaphysics. Carr’s Paradox of Subjectivity is organized into four parts. In the first part, Carr provides a synopsis of Heidegger’s interpretation of traditional metaphysics. Part two is devoted to a reconstruction of Kant’s transcendental theory of subjectivity. The third part deals with Husserl’s conception…Read more
  • Leibniz's Idealism and Husserl's Monadology
    Dissertation, State University of New York at Stony Brook. 2003.
    The dissertation deals with the historical and philosophical relationship between Leibniz and Husserl. The historical focus concerns Husserl's own interpretation and understanding of Leibniz as inferred from his logical writings, as well as his appropriation of the Leibnizian locutions, "monad" and "monadology." The philosophical concern deals with the relationship between epistemology and phenomenology. ;In the first portion of the paper, I address the problems of Leibniz's conceptualism. Towar…Read more
  •  23
    Presence and Origin: On the Possibility of the Static-Genetic Distinction
    Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 36 (2): 129-147. 2005.
    In this paper, I defend Husserl against Derrida's critique that Husserl's phenomenology is of a piece with the "the metaphysics of presence." I show much of Derrida's critique can be met by what Husserl calls "genetic phenomenology.".
  •  65
    Review: Nuzzo, Ideal embodiment: Kant's theory of sensibility
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 48 (2). 2010.
    This book is a survey of Kant's three Critiques that makes use of an "interpretive concept" that Nuzzo calls "transcendental embodiment" . According to Nuzzo, if we think of Kant as holding that there is something like the " a priori of the human body" or body as "the transcendental site of sensibility," which "displays a formal, ideal dimension essential to our experience as human beings" , then our understanding of Kant will be greatly improved. That is because the "notion of transcendental em…Read more
  •  62
    Leibniz on Concept and Substance
    International Philosophical Quarterly 46 (3): 309-325. 2006.
    A historically persistent way of reading Leibniz regards him as some kind of conceptualist. According to this interpretation, Leibniz was either an ontological conceptualist or an epistemological conceptualist. As an ontological conceptualist, Leibniz is taken to hold the view that there exist only concepts. As an epistemological conceptualist, he is seen as believing that we think only with concepts. I argue against both conceptualist renditions. I confront the ontological conceptualist view wi…Read more
  •  47
    Renato Cristin and kiyoshi Sakai, phänomenologie und Leibniz (review)
    Husserl Studies 20 (2): 161-166. 2004.
  •  17
    Ideal Embodiment: Kant's Theory of Sensibility (review) (review)
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 48 (2): 248-249. 2010.
    This book is a survey of Kant's three Critiques that makes use of an "interpretive concept" that Nuzzo calls "transcendental embodiment" . According to Nuzzo, if we think of Kant as holding that there is something like the " a priori of the human body" or body as "the transcendental site of sensibility," which "displays a formal, ideal dimension essential to our experience as human beings" , then our understanding of Kant will be greatly improved. That is because the "notion of transcendental em…Read more
  • In this paper, I show that by “Monade” the later Husserl means roughly what he meant by “das reine Bewußtsein” in the period of Ideas I. Of both consciousness and Monade, Husserl claims that objects of perception are immanent to them. I describe this claim as “quasi-representationalist” just because it bears enough similarity to some versions of contemporary representationalism. Since Husserl also claims that perceptual objects are publicly accessible, the inevitable conclusion seems to be that …Read more
  •  163
    The duality of non-conceptual content in Husserl’s phenomenology of perception
    Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 4 (2): 209-229. 2005.
    Recently, a number of epistemologists have argued that there are no non-conceptual elements in representational content. On their view, the only sort of non-conceptual elements are components of sub-personal organic hardware that, because they enjoy no veridical role, must be construed epistemologically irrelevant. By reviewing a 35-year-old debate initiated by Dagfinn F
  •  69
    Descartes and Husserl: The Philosophical Project of Radical Beginnings (review) (review)
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 38 (4): 593-595. 2000.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Descartes and Husserl. The Philosophical Project of Radical BeginningsMichael K. ShimPaul S. MacDonald. Descartes and Husserl. The Philosophical Project of Radical Beginnings. Albany: State University of New York Press, 2000. Pp. 285. Paper, $21.95.The enormous influence exerted by Descartes on Husserl's phenomenological philosophy cannot be underestimated. Not only is Husserl quite open and explicit about his philosophic…Read more
  •  51
    What kind of idealist was Leibniz?
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 13 (1). 2005.
    I argue Leibniz could not have been a dualist since his notion of matter is not defined by extension but by mentalistic "primitive passive force." So Leibniz was some kind of idealist. However, Leibniz was neither a phenomenal idealist like Berkeley nor a conceptualist idealist like Hegel. Instead, despite some suggestions in favor of the latter kind of idealism, Leibniz must be regarded as an idealist who admitted extraconceptual considerations irreducible to materialism
  • Jean-Luc Marion, Being Given (review)
    Philosophy in Review 23 262-264. 2003.