•  422
    This paper explores the relationships between perception, representation and appetition in Leibniz's later metaphysics, and defends four theses. First, for Leibniz perceptions are not the carriers of content, but they are identical to representational content. Second, Leibniz's appetitions are the carriers of content and he should be taken at his word when he declares, "Thought consists in conatus". Third, while it is true that for Leibniz representational content is determined by a species o…Read more
  •  358
    Plantinga and the Problem of Evil
    The Proceedings of the Twenty-First World Congress of Philosophy 8 109-113. 2006.
    The logical problem of evil centers on the apparent inconsistency of the following two propositions: God is omnipotent, omniscient, and wholly good, and There is evil in the world. This is the problem that Alvin Plantinga takes to task in his celebrated response to the problem of evil. Plantinga denies that and are inconsistent, arguing that J.L. Mackie's principle - that there are no limits to what an omnipotent thing can do - is false. We challenge Plantinga, and defend Mackie's view
  •  318
    The Preoccupation and Crisis of Analytic Philosophy
    European Journal of Analytic Philosophy 10 (1): 5-20. 2014.
    I propose to reconsider Gilbert Ryle’s thesis in 1956 in his introduction to The Revolution of Philosophy that “the story of twentieth-century philosophy is very largely the story of this notion of sense or meaning” and, as he writes elsewhere, the “preoccupation with the theory of meaning is the occupational disease of twentieth-century Anglo-Saxon and Austrian philoso- phy.” Ryle maintains that this preoccupation demar- cates analytic philosophy from its predecessors and that it gave philosoph…Read more
  •  205
    What God Could Have Made
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 43 (3): 355-376. 2005.
    Plantinga grants that there are possible worlds with freedom and no moral evil, but he argues that it is possible that although God is omnipotent, it is not within God’s power to actualize a world containing freedom and no moral evil. Plantinga believes that the atheologian assumes that it is necessary that it is within an omnipotent God’s power to actualize these better worlds, but in fact, Plantinga argues, this is demonstrably not the case. Since so many philosophers have regarded Plantinga’s…Read more
  •  166
    Frege’s ‘bedeutung’ and mill’s ‘denotatlon’
    Southwest Philosophy Review 20 (1): 139-145. 2004.
  •  125
    Wilhelm von Humboldt's classic study of human language was first published in 1836, as a general introduction to his three-volume treatise on the Kawi language of Java. It is the final statement of his lifelong study of the nature of language, exploring its universal structures and its relation to mind and culture. Empirically wide-ranging - Humboldt goes far beyond the Indo-European family of languages - it remains one of the most interesting and important attempts to draw philosophical conclus…Read more
  •  103
    Emdedded systems vs. individualism
    Minds and Machines 5 (3): 357-71. 1995.
    The dispute between individualism and anti-individualism is about the individuation of psychological states, and individualism, on some accounts, is committed to the claim that psychological subjects together with their environments do not constitute integrated computational systems. Hence on this view the computational states that explain psychological states in computational accounts of mind will not involve the subject''s natural and social environment. Moreover, the explanation of a system''…Read more
  •  102
    Individuation and the bundle theory
    Philosophical Studies 52 (2). 1987.
    It has been suggested that distinct individuals can have exactly the same properties; thus individuals cannot be individuated by their properties, And so the bundle theory appears to be false. One way to shore up the bundle theory is to introduce impure properties, And I defend this move against some objections by d m armstrong, M loux, And j van cleve
  •  98
    Leibniz and the rational order of nature (review)
    Philosophical Review 109 (1): 94-98. 2000.
    In this comprehensive study of Leibniz’s mature metaphysics, Donald Rutherford attempts to recover Leibniz’s theodicy as an essential part of his philosophy. Although Rutherford does not succeed in showing that the theodicy is essential to Leibniz’s metaphysics, he effectively uses the theodicy as an entry into Leibniz’s metaphysics and he highlights the many links between them. Of course, there are other significant ways of entering Leibniz’s philosophy—he wanted to “do justice to theology as t…Read more
  •  93
    Lenz on Locke on Language (review)
    Historiographia Linguistica 40 477-487. 2013.
    Review article of Martin Lenz, Locke's Sprachkonzeption, Berlin: de Gruyter, 2010.
  •  91
    Linguistic Turns in Modern Philosophy
    Cambridge University Press. 2006.
    This book traces the linguistic turns in the history of modern philosophy and the development of the philosophy of language from Locke to Wittgenstein. It examines the contributions of canonical figures such as Leibniz, Mill, Frege, Russell, Wittgenstein, Austin, Quine, and Davidson, as well as those of Condillac, Humboldt, Chomsky, and Derrida. Michael Losonsky argues that the philosophy of language begins with Locke's Essay Concerning Human Understanding. He shows how the history of the philos…Read more
  •  87
    The Completeness of Kant's Table of Judgments
    with Klaus Reich and Jane Kneller
    Duke University Press. 1992.
    English translation by Kneller and Losonsky of Klaus Reich, Die Vollständigkeit der Kantischen Urteilstafel "This classic of Kant scholarship, whose first edition appeared in 1932, deals with one of the most controversial and difficult topics in the Critique of Pure Reason: Kant's table of judgments and their connection to the table of categories. Kant's attempt to derive the latter from the former is called the "Metaphysical Deduction," and it paves the way for the Transcendental Deduction tha…Read more
  •  76
    The Nature of Artifacts
    Philosophy 65 (251). 1990.
    In Book II, Chapter 1 of the Physics Aristotle attempts to distinguish natural objects from artifacts. He begins by stating that a natural object ‘has in itself a source of change and staying unchanged, whether in respect of place, or growth and decay, or alteration’. But this is not sufficient to distinguish natural objects from artifacts. As he points out later, a wooden bed, for example, can rot or burn, and this is surely a change whose source is, in part, internal to the bed. To make his di…Read more
  •  76
    Aristotle on artifacts: A metaphysical puzzle (review)
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 79 (3): 445. 2001.
    Book Information Aristotle on Artifacts: A Metaphysical Puzzle. By Errol G. Katayama. State University of New York Press. Albany. 1999. Pp. xiii + 202. Paperback.
  •  65
    God, Property and Morality
    International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 10 (2). 1979.
  •  63
    John Locke on passion, will and belief
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 4 (2). 1996.
    No abstract
  •  62
    Kant believed that true enlightenment is the use of reason freely in public. This book systematicaaly traces the philosophical origins and development of the idea that the improvement of human understanding requires public activity. Michael Losonsky focuses on seventeenth-century discussions of the problem of irresolution and the closely connected theme of the role of volition in human belief formation. This involves a discussion of the work of Descartes, Hobbes, Locke, Spinoza and Leibniz. Chal…Read more
  •  56
    No problem for actualism
    Philosophical Review 95 (1): 95-97. 1986.
    Alan mcmichaels has argued that actualism, The view that there are no non-Actual entities, Has a problem with iterated modalities. This paper argues that this is not the case
  •  56
    Self-deceivers' intentions and possessions
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 20 (1): 121-122. 1997.
    Although Mele's four sufficient conditions for self-deception are on track insofar as they avoid the requirement that self-deception involves contradictory beliefs, they are too weak, because they are broad enough to include cases of bias or prejudice that are not typical cases of self-deception. I discuss what distinguishes self-deception from other forms of bias.
  •  52
    Locke and Leibniz on Religious Faith
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 20 (4). 2012.
    In the Essay Concerning Human Understanding, Locke maintains that ?Reason must be our last Judge and Guide in every Thing,? including matters of religious faith, and this commitment to the primacy of reason is not abandoned in his later religious writings. This essay argues that with regard to the relation between reason and religious faith, Locke is primarily concerned not with evidence, but with consistency, meaning, and how human beings ought to respond to their inclinations, including their …Read more
  •  50
    An Ontological Argument for Modal Realism
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 31 (1): 165-177. 1988.
    I argue for modal realism from the following principles:(R1) p just in case there are truth-makers for the proposition that p.(R2) If there are truth-makers for the proposition that p and the proposition that p relevantly entails the proposition that q, then there are truthrmakers for the proposition that q.(M) The proposition that p relevantly entails the proposition that possibly p.(R3) I f there are truth-makers for the proposition that q, then necessarily, if q, there are truth-makers for th…Read more
  •  47
    Roger Woolhouse, Locke: A Biography (review)
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 46 (1): 175-176. 2008.
    "A man of versatile mind"—a remark from a letter to Locke by a life-long friend—is the subtitle of the first chapter of this biography. It could also be the book's subtitle. Relying on Locke's correspondence, manuscripts, and mostly unpublished journals, Woolhouse pieces together a detailed quilt that exhibits the tremendous variety of Locke's interests and activities. Locke, who admitted to wandering interests , wrote about medicine, horticulture, religion, education, economics, government, and…Read more
  •  42
    Reasoned Freedom (review)
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 25 (2): 293-314. 1995.
  •  42
    This flexible textbook is both an introduction and a reader in metaphysics combining original discussion with selections from primary sources.
  •  42
    Individual Essences
    American Philosophical Quarterly 24 (3). 1987.
  •  41
    Passionate thought: Computation, thought and action in Hobbes
    Pragmatics and Cognition 1 (2): 245-266. 1993.
    According to a computational view of mind, thinking is identified with the manipulation of internal mental representations and intelligent behavior is the output of these computations. Although Thomas Hobbes's philosophy of mind is taken by many to be a precursor of this brand of cognitivism, this is not the case. For Hobbes, not all thinking is the manipulation of language-like symbols, and intelligent behavior is partly constitutive of cognition. Cognition requires a 'passionate thought', and …Read more
  •  37
    Abstraction, covariance, and representation
    Philosophical Studies 70 (2). 1993.
    According to a simple similarity theory of representation, x represents y because x and y share some properties. In Meaning and Mental Representation, Robert Cummins rejects this account for representations that play a role in cognition because, among other things, a similarity theory of representation precludes a satisfactory account of an essential cognitive task, namely abstraction. Intelligent beings have representations of classes and properties, and we need an account for such representati…Read more
  •  37
    Zeit der Ernte (review)
    Idealistic Studies 16 (1): 94-95. 1986.
    This is the fourth Festschrift for Arthur Hübscher, testifying to the respect and influence he enjoys. Hübscher edited the critical edition of Schopenhauer’s complete works and has been president of the Schopenhauer-Gesellschaft since 1936. This Festschrift is supposed to “document the state of international Schopenhauer scholarship for years to come”.