•  74
    The indispensability of farbung
    Synthese 138 (1). 2004.
    I offer a theory of propositional attitudeascriptions that reconciles a number of independently plausiblesemantic principles. At the heart of the theory lies the claim thatpsychological verbs (such as ``to believe'' and ``to doubt'') vary incontent indexically. After defending this claim and explaining how itrenders the aforementioned principles mutually compatible, I arguethat my account is superior to currently popular hidden indexicaltheories of attitude ascription. To conclude I indicate a n…Read more
  • Idealism: putting qualia to work
    In _Oxford Handbook of the Philosophy of Consciousness_, Oxford University Press. pp. 328-347. 2020.
  •  33
    Phenomenalism: A Metaphysics of Chance and Experience
    Oxford University Press, Oxford. 2022.
    J.S. Mill famously equated physical things with "permanent possibilities of sensation." This view, known as phenomenalism, holds that a rock is a tendency for experiences to occur as they do when people perceive a rock, and similarly for all other physical things. In _Phenomenalism_, Michael Pelczar develops Mill's theory in detail, defends it against the objections responsible for its current unpopularity, and uses it to shed light on important questions in metaphysics, the philosophy of scienc…Read more
  •  451
    The case for panpsychism: a critical assessment
    Synthese 200 (4): 1-22. 2022.
    According to panpsychists, physical phenomena are, at bottom, nothing but experiential phenomena. One argument for this view proceeds from an alleged need for physical phenomena to have features beyond what physics attributes to them; another starts by arguing that consciousness is ubiquitous, and proposes an identification of physical and experiential phenomena as the best explanation of this alleged fact. The first argument assumes that physical phenomena have categorical natures, and the seco…Read more
  •  888
    Modal arguments against materialism
    Noûs 55 (2): 426-444. 2021.
    We review existing strategies for bringing modal intuitions to bear against materialist theories of consciousness, and then propose a new strategy. Unlike existing strategies, which assume that imagination (suitably constrained) is a good guide to modal truth, the strategy proposed here makes no assumptions about the probative value of imagination. However, unlike traditional modal arguments, the argument developed here delivers only the conclusion that we should not believe that materialism is …Read more
  •  316
    Defending Phenomenalism
    Philosophical Quarterly 69 (276): 574-597. 2019.
    According to phenomenalism, physical things are a certain kind of possibility for experience. This paper clarifies the phenomenalist position and addresses some main objections to it, with the aim of showing that phenomenalism is a live option that merits a place alongside dualism and materialism in contemporary metaphysical debate.
  •  128
    Names as tokens and names as tools
    Synthese 128 (1-2). 2001.
    After presenting a variety of arguments in support of the idea that ordinary names are indexical, I respond to John Perry's recent arguments against the indexicality of names. I conclude by indicating some connections between the theory of names defended here and Wittgenstein's observations on naming, and suggest that the latter may have been misconstrued in the literature.
  •  465
    Someone who knew everything about the world’s physical nature could, apparently, suffer from ignorance about various aspects of conscious experience. Someone who knew everything about the world’s physical and mental nature could, apparently, suffer from moral ignorance. Does it follow that there are ways the world is, over and above the way it is physically or psychophysically? This paper defends a negative answer, based on a distinction between knowing the fact that p and knowing that p. This d…Read more
  •  366
    Must an Appearance of Succession Involve a Succession of Appearances?
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 81 (1): 49-63. 2010.
    It is argued that a subject who has an experience as of succession can have this experience at a time, or over a period of time, during which there occurs in him no succession of conscious mental states at all. Various metaphysical implications of this conclusion are explored. One premise of the main argument is that every experience is an experience as of succession. This implies that we cannot understand phenomenal temporality as a relation among experiences, but only as a primitive feature of…Read more
  •  56
    How does the modern scientific conception of time constrain the project of assigning the mind its proper place in nature? On the scientific conception, it makes no sense to speak of the duration of a pain, or the simultaneity of sensations occurring in different parts of the brain. Such considerations led Henri Poincaré, one of the founders of the modern conception, to conclude that consciousness does not exist in spacetime, but serves as the basic material out of which we must create the physic…Read more
  •  37
    Replies
    Analysis 76 (4): 479-501. 2016.
  •  103
    Enlightening the fully informed
    Philosophical Studies 126 (1): 29-56. 2005.
    This paper develops a response to the knowledge argument against physicalism. The response is both austere, in that it does not concede the existence of non-physical information , and natural, in that it acknowledges the alethic character of phenomenal knowledge and learning. I argue that such a response has all the advantages and none of the disadvantages of existing objections to the knowledge argument. Throughout, the goal is to develop a response that is polemically effective in addition to …Read more
  •  86
    Wittgensteinian semantics
    Noûs 34 (4). 2000.
    Wittgenstein emphasizes two points concerning his notion of family resemblance. One is that the use of a family resemblance expression resists characterization by certain kinds of rules; the other is that due to the prevalence of family resemblance in the philosophical lexicon, philosophical inquiry must in many cases proceed differently from how it traditionally has. This paper develops an interpretation of family resemblance that seeks to do justice to these claims. I argue that what is charac…Read more
  •  20
    Names as Tokens and Names as Tools
    Synthese 128 (1-2): 133-155. 2001.
    After presenting a variety of arguments in support of the idea that ordinary names are indexical, I respond to John Perry's recent arguments against the indexicality of names. I conclude by indicating some connections between the theory of names defended here and Wittgenstein's observations on naming, and suggest that the latter may have been misconstrued in the literature.
  •  45
    Summary
    Analysis 76 (4): 449-453. 2016.
  •  300
    Forms and objects of thought
    Linguistics and Philosophy 30 (1): 97-122. 2007.
    It is generally assumed that if it is possible to believe that p without believing that q, then there is some difference between the object of the thought that p and the object of the thought that q. This assumption is challenged in the present paper, opening the way to an account of epistemic opacity that improves on existing accounts, not least because it casts doubt on various arguments that attempt to derive startling ontological conclusions from seemingly innocent epistemic premises.
  •  43
    Critical Notices (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 72 (2): 480-483. 2007.
    Words without Meaning. CHRISTOPHER GAUKER. Cambridge, Massachusetts, and London, England.
  •  260
    On an argument for functional invariance
    Minds and Machines 18 (3): 373-377. 2008.
    The principle of functional invariance states that it is a natural law that conscious beings with the same functional organization have the same quality of conscious experience. A group of arguments in support of this principle are rejected, on the grounds that they establish at most only the weaker intra-subjective principle that any two stages in the life of a single conscious being that duplicate one another in terms of functional organization also duplicate one another in terms of quality of…Read more
  •  176
    Content Internalism about Indexical Thought
    American Philosophical Quarterly 46 (2). 2009.
    Properly understood, content internalism is the thesis that any difference between the representational contents of two individuals' mental states reduces to a difference in those individuals' intrinsic properties. Some of the strongest arguments against internalism turn on the possibility for two "doppelgangers" –- perfect physical and phenomenal duplicates -– to differ with respect to the contents of those of their mental states that they can express using terms such as "I," "here," and "now."…Read more
  •  173
    The indexical character of names
    with J. Rainsbury
    Synthese 114 (2): 293-317. 1998.
    Indexicals are unique among expressions in that they depend for their literal content upon extra-semantic features of the contexts in which they are uttered. Taking this peculiarity of indexicals into account yields solutions to variants of Frege's Puzzle involving objects of attitude-bearing of an indexical nature. If names are indexicals, then the classical versions of Frege's Puzzle can be solved in the same way. Taking names to be indexicals also yields solutions to tougher, more recently-di…Read more
  •  27
    Focal Complexity in Aristotle and Wittgenstein
    History of Philosophy Quarterly 21 (2). 2004.
  •  311
    Descartes' Dualism and Contemporary Dualism
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 46 (1): 145-160. 2010.
    After drawing a distinction between two kinds of dualism—numerical dualism (defined in terms of identity) and modal dualism (defined in terms of supervenience)—we argue that Descartes is a numerical dualist, but not a modal dualist. Since most contemporary dualists advocate modal dualism, the relation of Descartes' views to the contemporary philosophy of mind are more complex than is commonly assumed.
  •  307
    Normally, when we notice a change taking place, our conscious experience has a corresponding quality of phenomenal change. Here it is argued that one's experience can have this quality at or during a time when there is no change in which phenomenal properties one instantiates. This undermines a number of otherwise forceful arguments against leading metaphysical theories of change, but also requires these theories to construe change as a secondary quality, akin to color
  •  1
    Critical Notices
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 72 (2): 480-483. 2006.
    Words without Meaning is part of an ongoing effort by Christopher Gauker to give discursive norms pride of place over traditional relations of intentionality, representation, and meaning. In this book, he has a negative goal and a positive one. Negatively, he aims “to instill a sense of despair concerning the prospects” for making sense of the idea that brain states have propositional content. “The received view” is his collective term for theories that do treat beliefs as something like brain s…Read more