•  228
    Aristotle on the good for man
    Mind 90 (358): 243-262. 1981.
  •  208
    In "Metaphysics" Gamma 3 Aristotle declares that the philosopher investigates things that are qua things that are and that he therefore should be able to state the firmest principles of everything. The firmest principle of all is identified as the principle of non-contradiction (PNC). The main focus of Gamma 3 is Aristotle's proof for this identification. This paper begins with remarks about Aristotle's notion of the firmness of a principle and then offers an analysis of the firmness proof for P…Read more
  •  122
    Michael Wedin argues against the prevailing notion that Aristotle's views on the nature of reality are fundamentally inconsistent. According to Wedin's new interpretation, the difference between the early theory of the Categories and the later theory of the Metaphysics reflects the fact that Aristotle is engaged in quite different projects in the two works--the earlier focusing on ontology, and the later on explanation.
  •  121
    In On Generation and Corruption, Aristotle rejects the very possibility of such a thing as Anaximander’s apeiron. Characterized as a kind of intermediate stuff, the apeiron turns out to consist of contraries and as such is impossible. Commentators have rightly noted this point and some have also indicated that Aristotle offers an argument of sorts for his negative estimate. However, the argument has received scant attention, and it is fair to say that it remains unclear exactly why Aristotle rej…Read more
  •  111
    Negation and Quantification in Aristotle
    History and Philosophy of Logic 11 (2): 131-150. 1990.
    Two main claims are defended. The first is that negative categorical statements are not to be accorded existential import insofar as they figure in the square of opposition. Against Kneale and others, it is argued that Aristotle formulates his o statements, for example, precisely to avoid existential commitment. This frees Aristotle's square from a recent charge of inconsistency. The second claim is that the logic proper provides much thinner evidence than has been supposed for what appears to b…Read more
  •  73
    Collection and Division in the Phaedrus and Statesman
    Philosophical Inquiry 12 (1-2): 1-21. 1990.
  •  68
    PARTisanship in Metaphysics Z (review)
    Ancient Philosophy 11 (2): 361-385. 1991.
  •  65
  •  65
    Content and cause in the aristotelian mind
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 31 (S1): 49-105. 1993.
  •  56
    Nozick on Explaining Nothing
    Philosophy Research Archives 10 337-346. 1984.
    This paper raises some difficulties with the strategy suggested in Robert Nozick’s Philosophical Explanations for explaining why there is something rather than nothing. I am concerned less with his adoption of an egalitarian, as opposed to inegalitarian, explanatory stance (the net effect of which is to detach for independent consideration the question, “Why is there something?”) than with his use of a crucial assumption in reasoning from the egalitarian point of view. I argue that this assumpti…Read more
  •  54
    Nonsubstantial Individuals
    Phronesis 38 (2): 137-165. 1993.
  •  51
    Keeping the Matter in Mind: Aristotle on the Passions and the Soul
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 76 (3-4): 183-221. 1995.
    This paper considers I) whether Aristotle's notion of form is 'compositionally plastic' and II) whether matter is in any way to be included in the form of natural things. It pursues (I) and (II) with respect to two texts only: De Anima I-2's socalled definition of anger and the notorious young Socrates passage from Metaphysics VII.11. Neither passage supports indusion of anything material in the form and both are consistent with compositional plasticity. To thus extent the support what I call th…Read more
  •  50
    The Strategy of Aristotle’s Categories
    Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 79 (1): 1-26. 1997.
  •  45
    Critical Study (review)
    Ancient Philosophy 6 (n/a): 161-167. 1986.
  •  42
    The Origins of Aristotelian Science (review)
    Philosophical Review 102 (1): 87-89. 1993.
  •  42
  •  41
    Michael V. Wedin presents a rigorous reconstruction of the deductions in Parmenides' Way of Truth: the most important philosophical treatise before Plato and Aristotle. He answers criticisms which claim that Parmenides' arguments are shot through with logical fallacies, and argues against natural explanations of Parmenides in the Ionian tradition
  •  27
    Chapter 5. Aristotle on the Mind’s Self-Motion
    In Mary Louise Gill & James G. Lennox (eds.), Self-Motion: From Aristotle to Newton, Princeton University Press. pp. 81-116. 2017.
  •  24
    Singular Statements and Essentialism in Aristotle
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 14 (sup1): 67-88. 1984.
  •  22
  •  21
    Trouble in Paradise?
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 42 (1): 23-55. 1992.
    It is argued that Wittgenstein did not abandon his tractarian position because he was of the opinion that the Tractatus suffered from an intemal incoherence inherited from the incompatibility of the thesis of mutual independence of elementary propositions (MI) and the picture theory of the proposition (PIC) or an incoherent notion of the elementary proposition itself. In the way suggested, TLP provides no opportunity for such concems to arise, for the inner sub-surface structure of a proposition…Read more
  •  19
    Fred R. Berger: 1937 - 1986
    with Michael Bratman, Margaret Battin, Myles Brand, Julius Moravcsik, Richard Purtill, Anita Silvers, Richard Wasserstrom, and Elizabeth Wolgast
    Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 60 (3). 1987.
  •  17
    ‘Said of and ‘Predicated of' in the Categories
    Philosophy Research Archives 5 418-432. 1979.
    Anyone with more than casual interest in Aristotle's Categories knows the convention that "predicated of" ["κατηγορεἳται"] marks a general relation of predication while "said of" ["λέγεται"] is reserved for essential predication. By "convention" I simply mean to underscore that the view in question ranks as the conventional or received interpretation. Ackrill, for example, follows the received view in holding that only items within the same category (not arbitrarily, of course) can stand in the …Read more
  •  16
    Aristotle's views on the fundamental nature of reality are usually taken to be inconsistent. The two main sources for these views are the Categories and the central books of the Metaphysics, particularly book Zeta. In the early theory of the Categories the basic entities of the world are concrete objects such as Socrates: Aristotle calls them 'primary substances'. But the later theory awards this title to the forms of concrete objects. Michael Wedin proposes a compatibilist solution to this long…Read more
  •  16
    Aristotle's views on the fundamental nature of reality are usually taken to be inconsistent. The two main sources for these views are the Categories and the central books of the Metaphysics, particularly book Zeta. In the early theory of the Categories the basic entities of the world are concrete objects such as Socrates: Aristotle calls them 'primary substances'. But the later theory awards this title to the forms of concrete objects. Michael Wedin proposes a compatibilist solution to this long…Read more