•  5
    The Science and Axioms of Being
    In Georgios Anagnostopoulos (ed.), A Companion to Aristotle, Wiley‐blackwell. 2009.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Aristotle's Declaration of a General Science of Being qua Being A Problem for the Science of Being The Content of the General Science of Being Including Axioms in the General Science of Being The Notion of the Firmest Principle Proving Something about an Axiom: the Indubitability Proof of PNC PNC as the Ultimate Principle Defending an Axiom: the Elenctic Proof of PNC Theology and the General Science of Being Notes Bibliography.
  •  5
  •  14
    Trouble in Paradise?
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 42 (1): 23-55. 1992.
    It is argued that Wittgenstein did not abandon his tractarian position because he was of the opinion that the Tractatus suffered from an intemal incoherence inherited from the incompatibility of the thesis of mutual independence of elementary propositions (MI) and the picture theory of the proposition (PIC) or an incoherent notion of the elementary proposition itself. In the way suggested, TLP provides no opportunity for such concems to arise, for the inner sub-surface structure of a proposition…Read more
  •  21
    Trouble in Paradise?
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 42 (1): 23-55. 1992.
    It is argued that Wittgenstein did not abandon his tractarian position because he was of the opinion that the Tractatus suffered from an intemal incoherence inherited from the incompatibility of the thesis of mutual independence of elementary propositions (MI) and the picture theory of the proposition (PIC) or an incoherent notion of the elementary proposition itself. In the way suggested, TLP provides no opportunity for such concems to arise, for the inner sub-surface structure of a proposition…Read more
  •  17
    ‘Said of and ‘Predicated of' in the Categories
    Philosophy Research Archives 5 418-432. 1979.
    Anyone with more than casual interest in Aristotle's Categories knows the convention that "predicated of" ["κατηγορεἳται"] marks a general relation of predication while "said of" ["λέγεται"] is reserved for essential predication. By "convention" I simply mean to underscore that the view in question ranks as the conventional or received interpretation. Ackrill, for example, follows the received view in holding that only items within the same category (not arbitrarily, of course) can stand in the …Read more
  •  11
    Nozick on Explaining Nothing
    Philosophy Research Archives 10 337-346. 1984.
    This paper raises some difficulties with the strategy suggested in Robert Nozick’s Philosophical Explanations for explaining why there is something rather than nothing. I am concerned less with his adoption of an egalitarian, as opposed to inegalitarian, explanatory stance (the net effect of which is to detach for independent consideration the question, “Why is there something?”) than with his use of a crucial assumption in reasoning from the egalitarian point of view. I argue that this assumpti…Read more
  •  73
    Collection and Division in the Phaedrus and Statesman
    Philosophical Inquiry 12 (1-2): 1-21. 1990.
  •  5
    Criss-crossing a Philosophical Landscape
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 42 23-55. 1992.
    It is argued that Wittgenstein did not abandon his tractarian position because he was of the opinion that the Tractatus suffered from an intemal incoherence inherited from the incompatibility of the thesis of mutual independence of elementary propositions and the picture theory of the proposition or an incoherent notion of the elementary proposition itself. In the way suggested, TLP provides no opportunity for such concems to arise, for the inner sub-surface structure of a proposition cannot cau…Read more
  •  13
    Aristotle’s Theory of Substance: The Categories and Metaphysics Zeta
    Philosophical Quarterly 52 (207): 256-258. 2002.
  •  42
    The Origins of Aristotelian Science (review)
    Philosophical Review 102 (1): 87-89. 1993.
  •  56
    Nozick on Explaining Nothing
    Philosophy Research Archives 10 337-346. 1984.
    This paper raises some difficulties with the strategy suggested in Robert Nozick’s Philosophical Explanations for explaining why there is something rather than nothing. I am concerned less with his adoption of an egalitarian, as opposed to inegalitarian, explanatory stance (the net effect of which is to detach for independent consideration the question, “Why is there something?”) than with his use of a crucial assumption in reasoning from the egalitarian point of view. I argue that this assumpti…Read more
  •  65
  •  6
    Brill Online Books and Journals
    with Theodore Scaltsas, Michael J. White, Anna Ioppolo, Christopher Rowe, Bob Sharples, and Anne Sheppard
    Phronesis 38 (2): 137-165. 1993.
  •  16
    Aristotle's views on the fundamental nature of reality are usually taken to be inconsistent. The two main sources for these views are the Categories and the central books of the Metaphysics, particularly book Zeta. In the early theory of the Categories the basic entities of the world are concrete objects such as Socrates: Aristotle calls them 'primary substances'. But the later theory awards this title to the forms of concrete objects. Michael Wedin proposes a compatibilist solution to this long…Read more
  •  16
    Aristotle's views on the fundamental nature of reality are usually taken to be inconsistent. The two main sources for these views are the Categories and the central books of the Metaphysics, particularly book Zeta. In the early theory of the Categories the basic entities of the world are concrete objects such as Socrates: Aristotle calls them 'primary substances'. But the later theory awards this title to the forms of concrete objects. Michael Wedin proposes a compatibilist solution to this long…Read more
  • Parmendies' Three Ways and the Failure of the Ionian Interpretation
    Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 41 1-65. 2011.
  •  27
    Chapter 5. Aristotle on the Mind’s Self-Motion
    In Mary Louise Gill & James G. Lennox (eds.), Self-Motion: From Aristotle to Newton, Princeton University Press. pp. 81-116. 2017.
  •  22
  •  13
    Content and Cause in the Aristotelian Mind
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 31 (S1): 49-105. 1993.
  •  208
    In "Metaphysics" Gamma 3 Aristotle declares that the philosopher investigates things that are qua things that are and that he therefore should be able to state the firmest principles of everything. The firmest principle of all is identified as the principle of non-contradiction (PNC). The main focus of Gamma 3 is Aristotle's proof for this identification. This paper begins with remarks about Aristotle's notion of the firmness of a principle and then offers an analysis of the firmness proof for P…Read more
  •  50
    The Strategy of Aristotle’s Categories
    Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 79 (1): 1-26. 1997.