McGill University
Department of Philosophy
PhD, 1999
Richmond, Virginia, United States of America
Areas of Specialization
Epistemology
17th/18th Century Philosophy
  •  359
    The Value of a Free and Wandering Mind
    In Sebastian Schmidt & Gerhard Ernst (eds.), The Ethics of Belief and Beyond: Understanding Mental Normativity, Routledge. pp. 270-288. 2020.
    Miriam Schleifer McCormick delineates the limits, or at least one limit, of the ethics of mind. Many theorists, including McCormick herself, have argued that some states of mind are appropriate targets of certain reactive attitudes even if they cannot be directly controlled. McCormick now worries that the scope of agency can be widened too far so that no area of mind is beyond the reach of appropriate assessment and judgement. She begins with the intuition that there is, or ought to be, a…Read more
  •  315
  •  184
    Taking control of belief
    Philosophical Explorations 14 (2): 169-183. 2011.
    I investigate what we mean when we hold people responsible for beliefs. I begin by outlining a puzzle concerning our ordinary judgments about beliefs and briefly survey and critique some common responses to the puzzle. I then present my response where I argue a sense needs to be articulated in which we do have a kind of control over our beliefs if our practice of attributing responsibility for beliefs is appropriate. In developing this notion of doxastic control, I draw from John Fischer's discu…Read more
  •  134
    Why Should We Be Wise?
    Hume Studies 31 (1): 3-19. 2005.
    There is a tension in Hume’s theory of belief. He tells us that beliefs are ideas that, as a result of certain natural mechanisms of the mind, become particularly lively and vivacious. Such an account seems to allow us little control over which beliefs we acquire, maintain or eschew. It seems I could not avoid feeling the strength of such ideas any more than I could avoid feeling the strength of the sun when exposed to it. Yet much of Hume’s writings on belief reveal that he thinks we do have qu…Read more
  •  70
    Hume on Natural Belief and Original Principles
    Hume Studies 19 (1): 103-116. 1993.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Hume on Natural Belief and Original Principles Miriam McCormick David Hume discusses anumber ofimportantbeliefs that, althoughhe himselfnever uses the term, commentators have come to call "natural beUefs." These beliefs cannotbejustified rationally but are impossible to give up. They differ from irrational beliefs because no amount of reasoning can eliminate them. There is general agreement that such a class of beliefs exists for Hum…Read more
  •  53
    A Change in Manner: Hume's Scepticism in the Treatise and the first Enquiry
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 29 (3): 431-447. 1999.
    The year before his death, Hume asked his publisher to affix an advertisement to all existing and future editions of his works. In this advertisement, Hume disavows the Treatise and directs all criticism to his later work. Hume himself is relatively clear as to why he preferred this later work. In his autobiography, when discussing the poor public reception given his Treatise, Hume says, ‘I had always entertained a Notion, that my want of Success in publishing the Treatise of human nature, had p…Read more
  •  50
    Compelled Belief
    American Philosophical Quarterly 42 (3): 157-169. 2005.
    None
  •  33
    A Change in Manner: Hume’s Scepticism in the Treatise and the first Enquiry
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 29 (3): 431-447. 1999.
    The year before his death, Hume asked his publisher to affix an advertisement to all existing and future editions of his works. In this advertisement, Hume disavows the Treatise and directs all criticism to his later work. Hume himself is relatively clear as to why he preferred this later work. In his autobiography, when discussing the poor public reception given his Treatise, Hume says, ‘I had always entertained a Notion, that my want of Success in publishing the Treatise of human nature, had p…Read more
  •  29
    The Mind of David Hume: A Companion to Book I of a Treatise of Human Nature
    Review of Metaphysics 51 (1): 161-161. 1997.
    Oliver Johnson’s book is the first attempt to offer a systematic textual analysis of Book 1 of The Treatise, in which he seeks to fill “an important gap in the literature on Hume” by undertaking “the task of going through Book I fully, systematically, and in detail, following directly in the footsteps of Hume”.
  •  19
    Book Review: Moore and Wittgenstein: Scepticism, Certainty and Common Sense, written by Annalisa Coliva (review)
    International Journal for the Study of Skepticism 5 (4). 2015.
    _ Source: _Page Count 6
  •  19
    Are We Responsible for Our Emotions and Moods?
    with Michael Schleifer
    Thinking: The Journal of Philosophy for Children 18 (1): 15-21. 2006.
  •  12
    Responsibility for Beliefs and Emotions
    with Michael Schleifer
    Paideusis: Journal of the Canadian Philosophy of Education Society 15 (1): 75-85. 2006.
    This paper maintains that the concept of responsibility must be extended to beliefs and emotions. It argues that beliefs and emotions have their crucial link through the element of judgment. Judgment refers to relationships in contexts of ambiguity and uncertainty; developing good judgment in children involves the question of similarities and differences in varying situations and contexts. Both beliefs and emotions are crucial to this process. Educators interested in helping develop better judgm…Read more
  •  9
    Peter S. Fosl, Hume's Scepticism: Pyrrhonian and Academic (review)
    Journal of Scottish Philosophy 19 (3): 280-285. 2021.