•  263
    Just a paradigm: evidence-based medicine in epistemological context
    European Journal for Philosophy of Science 1 (3): 451-466. 2011.
    Evidence-Based Medicine (EBM) developed from the work of clinical epidemiologists at McMaster University and Oxford University in the 1970s and 1980s and self-consciously presented itself as a "new paradigm" called "evidence-based medicine" in the early 1990s. The techniques of the randomized controlled trial, systematic review and meta-analysis have produced an extensive and powerful body of research. They have also generated a critical literature that raises general concerns about its methods.…Read more
  •  254
    Trust in the practice of rational deliberation is widespread and largely unquestioned. This paper uses recent work from business contexts to challenge the view that rational deliberation in a group improves decisions. Pressure to reach consensus can, in fact, lead to phenomena such as groupthink and to suppression of relevant data. Aggregation of individual decisions, rather than deliberation to a consensus, surprisingly, can produce better decisions than those of either group deliberation or in…Read more
  •  246
    Norms of epistemic diversity
    Episteme 3 (1-2): 23-36. 2006.
    Epistemic diversity is widely approved of by social epistemologists. This paper asks, more specifi cally, how much epistemic diversity, and what kinds of epistemic diversity are normatively appropriate? Both laissez-faire and highly directive approaches to epistemic diversity are rejected in favor of the claim that diversity is a blunt epistemic tool. There are typically a number of diff erent options for adequate diversifi cation. The paper focuses on scientifi c domains, with particular attent…Read more
  •  176
    It Isn't The Thought That Counts
    Argumentation 15 (1): 67-75. 2001.
  •  169
    Scientific rationality and human reasoning
    Philosophy of Science 59 (3): 439-455. 1992.
    The work of Tversky, Kahneman and others suggests that people often make use of cognitive heuristics such as availability, salience and representativeness in their reasoning and decision making. Through use of a historical example--the recent plate tectonics revolution in geology--I argue that such heuristics play a crucial role in scientific decision making also. I suggest how these heuristics are to be considered, along with noncognitive factors (such as motivation and social structures) when …Read more
  •  145
    Social empiricism
    Noûs 28 (3): 325-343. 1994.
    A new, social epistemology of science that addresses practical as well as theoretical concerns.
  •  143
    Consensus in Science
    The Proceedings of the Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 10 193-204. 2001.
    Because the idea of consensus in contemporary philosophy of science is typically seen as the locus of progress, rationality, and, often, truth, Mill’s views on the undesirability of consensus have been largely dismissed. The historical data, however, shows that there are many examples of scientific progress without consensus, thus refuting the notion that consensus in science has any special epistemic status for rationality, scientific progress (success), or truth. What needs to be developed ins…Read more
  •  88
    A Critical Context For Longino’s Critical Contextual Empiricism
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 36 (1): 211-222. 2005.
  •  75
    Legend naturalism and scientific progress: An essay on Philip Kitcher's
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 26 (2): 205-218. 1995.
    Philip Kitcher's The Advancement of Science sets out, programmatically, a new naturalistic view of science as a process of building consensus practices. Detailed historical case studies—centrally, the Darwinian revolutio—are intended to support this view. I argue that Kitcher's expositions in fact support a more conservative view, that I dub ‘Legend Naturalism’. Using four historical examples which increasingly challenge Kitcher's discussions, I show that neither Legend Naturalism, nor the less …Read more
  •  70
    Responses to critics
    Perspectives on Science 16 (3). 2008.
    In this paper I respond to the criticisms of Helen Longino, Alan Richardson, Naomi Oreskes and Sharyn Clough. There is discussion of the character of social knowledge, the goals of scientific inquiry, the connections between Social Empiricism and other approaches in science studies, productive and unproductive dissent, and the distinction between empirical and non-empirical decision vectors.
  •  69
    Enlightened Empiricism: An Examination of W. V. Quine's Theory of Knowledge (review)
    Philosophical Review 100 (3): 484-487. 1991.
  •  68
    Review of Anya Plutynski’s Explaining cancer: finding order in disorder (review)
    Biology and Philosophy 34 (3): 37. 2019.
    Anya Plutynski’s Explaining Cancer extends the insights of contemporary philosophy of biology to research on cancer and cancer treatment. Cancer is conceptualized as a complex process for which a pluralist theoretical approach is the most appropriate. This review essay explores implications for philosophy of science and cancer research.
  •  60
    A development of Quine's views took place between the denial of analyticity (in "Two Dogmas") and the doctrine of indeterminacy (in Word and Object). Quine argues for the inscrutability of extensional as well as intensional content. The debate with Carnap in the mid-fifties pushes Quine to argue for full indeterminacy. Quine initially resists arguing for indeterminacy because the doctrine seems to lead to general skepticism, not just to skepticism about meanings. Quine draws on Tarski's work on …Read more
  •  58
    Quine's point of view
    Journal of Philosophy 86 (3): 113-136. 1989.
    Quine claims to be "working from within" our conceptual scheme and proceeding scientifically. This description makes his views of interest to those who are skeptical of traditional metaphysical projects and to those with confidence in science. This study examines whether Quine is in fact starting within ordinary language and proceeding scientifically and, if not, how his views are to be best understood. I proceed by exploring some central doctrines in Quine's writing, most notably indeterminacy …Read more
  •  55
    Commentary on Alison Gopnik's "the scientist as child"
    Philosophy of Science 63 (4): 547-551. 1996.
    None
  •  42
    Trust: The Need for Public Understanding of How Science Works
    Hastings Center Report 51 (S1): 36-39. 2021.
    General science literacy contributes to good public decision‐making about technology and medicine. This essay explores the kinds of science literacy currently developed by public education in the United States of America. It argues that current curricula on “science as inquiry” (formerly the “nature of science”) need to be brought up to date with the inclusion of discussion of social epistemological concepts such as trust and scientific authority, scientific disagreement versus science denialism…Read more
  •  41
    The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Medicine (edited book)
    with Jeremy R. Simon and Harold Kincaid
    Routledge. 2016.
    _The_ _Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Medicine _is a comprehensive guide to topics in the fields of epistemology and metaphysics of medicine. It examines traditional topics such as the concept of disease, causality in medicine, the epistemology of the randomized controlled trial, the biopsychosocial model, explanation, clinical judgment and phenomenology of medicine and emerging topics, such as philosophy of epidemiology, measuring harms, the concept of disability, nursing perspectives, ra…Read more
  •  39
    Multivariate Models of Scientific Change
    PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1994. 1994.
    Social scientists regularly make use of multivariate models to describe complex social phenomena. It is argued that this approach is useful for modelling the variety of cognitive and social factors contributing to scientific change, and superior to the integrated models of scientific change currently available. It is also argued that care needs to be taken in drawing normative conclusions: cognitive factors are not instrinsically more "rational" than social factors, nor is it likely that social …Read more
  •  35
    On Putnam’s Argument for the Inconsistency of Relativism
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 28 (2): 213-220. 1990.
  •  35
    The whiptail lizard reconsidered
    Perspectives on Science 11 (3): 318-325. 2003.
    : Harry Collins and Trevor Pinch's introductory text, The Golem: What Everyone Should Know About Science (1993), includes a controversy about the significance of pseudosexual behavior in the parthenogenetic whiptail lizard. Collins and Pinch, basing their account on the work of Greg Myers (1990), claim that "in this area of biology, experiments are seldom possible" and that the debate has "battled to an honorable draw." I argue that a closer look at the publications of the scientists involved sh…Read more
  •  32
    Born to Rebel. Frank Sulloway
    Philosophy of Science 65 (1): 171-181. 1998.
    Born to Rebel is an innovative and important work with much to say to philosophers of science, as well as historians and sociologists of science. Sulloway uses, successfully, quantitative statistical methods that others have despaired of using to analyze the complexities of historical change. In particular, he investigates scientific decision-making during scientific controversies with a multivariate analysis. The goal is to discern, precisely, the contribution of factors such as religious belie…Read more
  •  29
    Norms of Epistemic Diversity
    Episteme: A Journal of Social Epistemology 3 (1): 23-36. 2006.
    Epistemic diversity is widely approved of by social epistemologists. This paper asks, more specifically, how much epistemic diversity, and what kinds of epistemic diversity are normatively appropriate? Bothlaissez-faireand highly directive approaches to epistemic diversity are rejected in favor of the claim that diversity is a blunt epistemic tool. There are typically a number of different options for adequate diversification. The paper focuses on scientific domains, with particular attention to…Read more
  •  24
    Social Empiricism
    MIT Press. 2001.
    For the last forty years, two claims have been at the core of disputes about scientific change: that scientists reason rationally and that science is progressive. For most of this time discussions were polarized between philosophers, who defended traditional Enlightenment ideas about rationality and progress, and sociologists, who espoused relativism and constructivism. Recently, creative new ideas going beyond the polarized positions have come from the history of science, feminist criticism of …Read more