•  53
    هراکلیتوس (Ἡράκλειτος) گزیده ای از پاره ها و شواهد دنیل گراهام ترجمه محمد باقر قمی
  •  19
    ملیسوس (Μέλισσος) گزیده ای از پاره ها و شواهد دنیل گراهام ترجمه محمد باقر قمی
  •  57
    گزنوفانس (Ξενοφάνης) گزیده ای از پاره ها و شواهد دنیل گراهام ترجمه محمد باقر قمی
  •  47
    گرگیاس (Γοργίας) گزیده ای از پاره ها و شواهد دنیل گراهام ترجمه محمد باقر قمی
  •  52
    زنون (Ζήνων) گزیده ای از پاره ها و شواهد دنیل گراهام ترجمه محمد باقر قمی
  •  60
    لئوکیپوس (Λεύκιππος) و دموکریتوس (Δημόκριτος) گزیده ای از پاره ها و شواهد دنیل گراهام ترجمه محمد باقر قمی
  •  57
    تالس (Θαλῆς) گزیده ای از پاره ها و شواهد دنیل گراهام ترجمه محمد باقر قمی
  •  54
    پروتاگوراس (Πρωταγόρας) گزیده ای از پاره ها و شواهد دنیل گراهام ترجمه محمد باقر قمی
  •  59
    آناکسیمنس (Ἀναξιμένης) گزیده ای از پاره ها و شواهد دنیل گراهام ترجمه محمد باقر قمی
  •  67
    آناکسیماندروس (Ὰναξἰμανδρος) گزیده ای از پاره ها و شواهد دنیل گراهام ترجمه محمد باقر قمی
  •  60
    پارمنیدس (Παρμενίδης) گزیده ای از پاره ها و شواهد دنیل گراهام ترجمه محمد باقر قمی
  •  58
    آناکساگوراس (ναξαγόραςἈ) گزیده ای از پاره ها و شواهد دنیل گراهام ترجمه محمد باقر قمی
  •  47
    امپدکلس (Ἐμπεδοκλῆς) گزیده ای از پاره ها و شواهد دنیل گراهام ترجمه محمد باقر قمی
  •  51
    پیش گفتار سالها پیش (حدود سال 1395) برخی از مهمترین پاره های پیش سقراطیان را از روی کتاب گراهام برای درک بهتر خودم از آن پاره ها ترجمه کرده بودم. اکنون به نظرم رسید شاید این ترجمه بتواند برای برخی دانشجویان و علاقمندان به فلسفه مفید باشد. به همین دلیل تصمیم به انتشار آن در اینترنت گرفتم. هرچند در ترجمه ها متن یونانی را مبنا قرار داده ام اما به دلیل دانش ناقصم از زبان یونانی، هرجا که نتوانستم زبان یونانی را مبنا قرار دهم از ترجمه انگلیسی آن استفاده کردم. از آنجا که این کار به قصد انتشار انجام نشد…Read more
  •  82
    In Physics (Δ, 3, 210a14-24) Aristotle distinguishes eight senses in which one thing is said to be in another thing: 1. Part in whole; e.g. finger in hand 2. The whole in its parts: ‘For there is no whole over and above the parts.’ 3. Species in genus; e.g. man in animal 4. Genus in species (generally: the part of the specific form in the definition of the specific form) 5. Form in matter; e.g. health in the hot and the cold 6. Event in its primary motive agent; e.g. the affairs of Greece center…Read more
  •  120
    Aristotle distinguishes between four causes (Phy., B, 3; PsA, B, 11, 94a20-24): a) Material cause: that from which; the antecedent out of which a thing comes to be and persists. E.g. the bronze of the statue; the silver of the bowl b) Formal cause: essence; the form or the archetype, i.e. the statement of the essence and its genera and the parts in definition; the whole and the co-positing. E.g. the relation 2:1 and generally number as cause of the octave c) Efficient cause: the primary source …Read more
  •  4
    A. Knowledge and universal The points about the relationship between knowledge and universal in Aristotle’s philosophy can be inferred as such: 1. Knowledge of a universal includes knowledge of all its subordinates (τὰ ὑποκείμενα) in a sense. (Met., A, 982a21-23) The converse of this is not true because ‘highest universals (τὰ πρῶτα) and causes are not known by things subordinate to them (τῶν ὑποκειμένων). (Met., A, 982b2-4) 2. Knowledge is bound up severely with universality: ‘For all things t…Read more
  •  802
    Thought (νοῦς) for Aristotle is ‘that whereby the soul thinks and judges.’ This identity, however, ‘is not actually any real thing before thinking’ (ἐνεργείᾳ τῶν ὄντων πρὶν νοεῖν) and, thus, cannot reasonably be regarded as blended with the body and cannot acquire any quality or have any organ. (So., Γ, 4, 429a22-27) In fact, Aristotle defines thought more with a capability: ‘That which is capable of receiving the object of thought, i.e. the substance, is thought.’ (Met., Λ, 1072b22-23) Though…Read more
  •  195
    Aristotle defines motion as such: ‘The fulfillment of what exists potentially, in so far as it exist potentially, is motion.’ (Phy., Γ, 1, 201a10-11) He defines it again in the same chapter: ‘It is the fulfillment of what is potential when it is already fully real and operates not as itself but as movable, that is motion. What I mean by ‘as’ is this: Bronze is potentially a statue. But it is not the fulfillment of bronze as bronze which is motion.’ (Phy., Γ, 1) 2) Motion: not a real thing Arist…Read more
  •  140
    At the very beginning of On Interpretation (I, 1, 16a3-14) Aristotle distinguishes four levels and discusses their relationships. From this text, we can infer the following: 1. There are four levels: writing, speaking, mental experience and external world. Since writing and speaking can truly be taken as belonging to the same realm, we can reduce Aristotle’s distinction to three realms: language, thought and external world. 2. The realm of language, in both levels of writing and speaking, is dif…Read more
  •  113
    It seems that by ‘having meaning’ or ‘significating’ (σημαίνειν) Aristotle has something like kind of determination in mind: ‘If ‘man’ has one meaning, let this be ‘two-footed animal’; by having one meaning I understand this: If such and such is a man, then if anything is a man, that will be what being a man is (τοῦτ’ ἔσται τὸ ἄνθρώπῳ εἶναι).’ (Met., Γ, 1006a31-34) This also brings kind of whole-particular or class-member relationship to mind: if a word has one meaning, everything that is a par…Read more
  •  129
    It seems that there is a general principle in Aristotle’s philosophy that ‘all things are referred to that which is primary (πὰντα πρὸς τὸ πρῶτον ἀναφέρεται).’ (Met., Γ, 1004a25-26) This referring relation, however, may be in a different way for each thing: ‘After distinguishing the various senses of each, we must then explain by reference to what is primary in each term, saying how they are related to it; some in the sense that they possess it, others in the sense that they produce it…’ (Met.,…Read more
  •  66
    Aristotle’s points about circle and vicious circle are as follows: 1. Aristotle criticizes some thinkers because ‘they see no difficulty in holding that all truths are demonstrated, on the ground that demonstration may be circular and reciprocal.’ (PsA., A, 3, 72b16-18) 2. ‘Not all knowledge is demonstrative’ and ‘knowledge of the immediate premises is independent of demonstration.’ Aristotle brings two reasons for this: ‘Since we must know the prior premises from which the demonstration is dra…Read more
  •  93
    Thought is the primary realm in which truth and falsity may occur and speech the secondary realm of this occurrence while the realm of external being has no truth and falsity in itself. The first and last points are directly asserted by Aristotle in one text: ‘Falsity and truth are not in things-it is not as if the good were true, and the bad were in itself false- but in thought.’ (Met., E, 1027b25-27; cf. Met., K, 1065a22-23) The second point is also somehow implied: ‘As there are in the mind …Read more
  •  161
    Aristotle’s process of constituting the notion of time through Phy., Δ, 10 to Phy., Δ, 12 has the following steps: 1) Time and not-being Since one part of time ‘has been and is not, while the other is going to be and is not yet … one would naturally suppose that what is made up of things which do not exist could have no share in reality.’ (Phy., Δ, 10) 2) Time, divisibility and now We should not regard time as something divisible to parts, some of which belong to past and some other to future. …Read more
  •  50
    However, there are a few points about what we can call ‘relation’ in Aristotle’s works: 1. Sound is always of something in relation to something and in something and it is impossible for one body only to generate a sound. (So., B, 8, 419b9-10) 2. Corresponding relation: ‘Let then C be to D as A, white, is to B, black; it follows alternado that C:A :: D:B. if then C and A belong to one subject, the case will be the same with them as with D and B…’ 3. ‘And the case is similar in regard to the sta…Read more
  •  58
    1. ‘But occasionally it happens that we get a sudden idea and recollect that we heard or saw something formerly. This happens whenever, from contemplating a mental object in itself, one changes his point of view, and regards it as relative to something else.’ 2. ‘Recollection is not the recovery or acquisition of memory; since at the instant when one at first learns or experiences, he does not thereby recover a memory inasmuch as none has preceded, nor does he acquire one ab initio.’ (OM., 451…Read more
  •  61
    In Physics (Δ, 4, 210b34-211a6) Aristotle enumerates five features of place: i. Place is what contains that of which it is the place. ii. Place is not part of the thing it is its place. (Also cf. Phy., Δ, 2) iii. The immediate place of a thing is neither less nor greater than the thing. iv. Place can be left behind by the thing and is separable. (Also cf. Phy., Δ, 2) Aristotle connects our understanding of place with locomotion: ‘place would not have been thought of, if there had not been a spe…Read more
  •  184
    There are at least two discussions about Pythagoreans in Aristotle’s works that can be related to paradigm, both in Book A of Metaphysics. In the first, Aristotle says that for Pythagoreans all the things are modeled after numbers (τὰ μὲν ἄλλα τοῖς ἀριθμοῖς ἐφαίνετο τὴν φύσιν ἀφωμοιῶσθαι πᾶσιν). (Met., A, 985b32-33) In the second, Aristotle tells us that Pythagoreans take ‘the first subject of which a given term would be predicable (ᾧ πρώτῳ ὑπάρξειεν ὁ λεχθεὶς ὃρος)’ as the substance of the thi…Read more
  •  71
    Aristotle’s points about memory are as follows: 1. ‘Memory even of intellectual objects involves an image and the image is an affection of the common senses. Thus memory belongs incidentally to the faculty of thought, and essentially it belongs to the primary faculty of sense-perception.’ (OM., 450a^10-13) 2. The fact that animals have memory proves that it is a function of sense perception and not thought: ‘If memory were a function of the thinking parts, it would not have been an attribute of…Read more