•  14
    The Good and the True (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 55 (2): 494-496. 1995.
  •  38
    Evidence and Assurance
    Cambridge University Press. 1980.
    A systematic study of rational or justified belief, which throws fresh light on current debates about foundations and coherence theories of knowledge, the validation of induction and moral scepticism. Dr Nathan focuses attention on the largely unsatisfiable desires for active and self-conscious assurance of truth liable to be engendered by philosophical reflection about total belief-systems and the sources of knowledge. He extracts a kernel of truth from the doctrine that a regress of justificat…Read more
  •  25
  •  27
    Metaphysics
    with Gabriel Uzquiano
    Philosophical Books 46 (3): 268-271. 2005.
  •  67
    Admiration: A New Obstacle
    Philosophy 72 (281). 1997.
  •  22
    Common Sense Metaphysics
    Philosophy 46 (176). 1971.
  •  2
    VIII*—Democracy
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 93 (1): 123-138. 1993.
    N. M. L. Nathan; VIII*—Democracy, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 93, Issue 1, 1 June 1993, Pages 123–138, https://doi.org/10.1093/aristotelian/
  •  37
    VI*—Scepticism and the Regress of Justification
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 75 (1): 77-88. 1975.
    N. M. L. Nathan; VI*—Scepticism and the Regress of Justification, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 75, Issue 1, 1 June 1975, Pages 77–88, https:/
  •  6
    Critical Notices
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 70 (3): 735-748. 2007.
  •  125
    The Multiplication of Utility: N. M. L. Nathan
    Utilitas 6 (2): 217-218. 1994.
    Some people have supposed that utility is good in itself, non-in-strumentally good, as distinct from good because conducive to other good things. And in modern versions of this view, utility often means want-satisfaction, as distinct from pleasure or happiness. For your want that p to be satisfied, is it necessary that you know or believe that p, or sufficient merely that p is true? However that question is answered, there are problems with the view that want-satisfaction is a non-instrumental g…Read more
  •  12
    Some prerequisites for a political casuistry of justice
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 13 (1-4). 1970.
    After briefly vindicating casuistries which successively apply a number of different moral principles, I describe some of the principles of justice liable to figure in such casuistries, assess the relative popularity of these principles and show that some of the most popular cannot be consistently applied in all circumstances.
  •  87
    Substance Dualism Fortified
    Philosophy 86 (2): 201-211. 2011.
    You have a body, but you are a soul or self. Without your body, you could still exist. Your body could be and perhaps is outlasted by the immaterial substance which is your soul or self. Thus the substance dualist. Most substance dualists are Cartesians. The self, they suppose, is essentially conscious: it cannot exist unless it thinks or wills or has experiences. In this paper I sketch out a different form of substance dualism. I suggest that it is not consciousness but another immaterial featu…Read more
  •  45
    Self and will
    International Journal of Philosophical Studies 5 (1). 1997.
    When do two mental items belong to the same life? We could be content with the answer -just when they have certain volitional qualities in common. An affinity is noted between that theory and Berkeley's early doctrine of the self. Some rivals of the volitional theory invoke a spiritual or physical owner of mental items. They run a risk either of empty formality or of causal superstition. Other rivals postulate a non-transitive and symmetrical relation in the set of mental items. They must allow …Read more
  •  30
    Projectivist utilitarianism
    Erkenntnis 20 (2). 1983.
  •  18
    Projectivist utilitarianism: Reply to Gordon (review)
    Erkenntnis 26 (1). 1987.
  •  56
    On the Justification of Democracy
    The Monist 55 (1): 89-120. 1971.
    1. The ideal of spatio-temporally unrestricted generalisation, which marks all post-mythological thinking about nature, marks no more than the continuity of totemism in political casuistry. No unrestricted principle of Socialism or Conservatism or Liberal Democracy is defensible unless it is accorded a moral ultimacy which almost no one fully conscious of what he was about would actually want to accord it. If this bare platitude is to be fully assimilated, it needs both concrete exemplification …Read more
  • No Title available: Reviews
    Philosophy 83 (1): 145-149. 2008.
  •  32
    On the non-causal explanation of human action
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 6 (3): 241-243. 1976.
  •  41
    Necessity, Inconceivability and the "A Priori"
    with J. J. Valberg
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 56 (1). 1982.
  •  66
    Mctaggart's immaterialism
    Philosophical Quarterly 41 (165): 442-456. 1991.
  •  91
    Naturalism and self-defeat: Plantinga's version
    Religious Studies 33 (2): 135-142. 1997.
    In "Warrant and Proper Function" Plantinga argues that atheistic Naturalism is self-defeating. What is the probability that our cognitive faculties are reliable, given this Naturalism and an evolutionary explanation of their origins? Plantinga argues that if the Naturalist is modest enough to believe that it is irrational to have any belief as to the value of this probability, then he is irrational even to believe his own Naturalism. I suggest that Plantinga's argument has a false premise, and t…Read more
  •  71
    Murder and the death of Christ
    Think 9 (26): 103-107. 2010.
    Some people believe that God made it a condition for His forgiveness even of repentant sinners that Jesus died a sacrificial death at human hands. Often, in the New Testament, this doctrine of Objective Atonement seems to be implied, as when Jesus spoke of his blood as ‘shed for many for the remission of sins’ , or when St Paul said that ‘Christ died for our sins according to the scriptures’ . And for many centuries the doctrine was indeed accepted by most if not all Christian theologians. It se…Read more
  •  210
    Materialism and action
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 35 (4): 501-511. 1975.